% %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% % % % % Project Gutenberg's The Mathematical Analysis of Logic, by George Boole % % % % This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere at no cost and with % % almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or % % re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included % % with this eBook or online at book.klll.cc % % % % % % Title: The Mathematical Analysis of Logic % % Being an Essay Towards a Calculus of Deductive Reasoning % % % % Author: George Boole % % % % Release Date: July 28, 2011 [EBook #36884] % % Most recently updated: June 11, 2021 % % % % Language: English % % % % Character set encoding: UTF-8 % % % % *** START OF THIS PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK THE MATHEMATICAL ANALYSIS OF LOGIC *** % % % %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% % \def\ebook{36884} %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% %% %% %% Packages and substitutions: %% %% %% %% book: Required. %% %% inputenc: Latin-1 text encoding. Required. %% %% babel: Greek language capabilities. Required. %% %% %% %% ifthen: Logical conditionals. Required. %% %% %% %% amsmath: AMS mathematics enhancements. Required. %% %% amssymb: Additional mathematical symbols. Required. %% %% %% %% alltt: Fixed-width font environment. Required. %% %% array: Enhanced tabular features. Required. %% %% %% %% indentfirst: Indent first line of section. Required. %% %% footmisc: Start footnote numbering on each page. Required. %% %% %% %% caption: Caption customization for table. Required. %% %% %% %% calc: Length calculations. Required. %% %% %% %% fancyhdr: Enhanced running headers and footers. Required. %% %% %% %% geometry: Enhanced page layout package. Required. %% %% hyperref: Hypertext embellishments for pdf output. Required. %% %% %% %% %% %% Producer's Comments: %% %% %% %% OCR text for this ebook was obtained on July 25, 2011, from %% %% http://www.archive.org/details/mathematicalanal00booluoft. %% %% %% %% Minor changes to the original are noted in this file in three %% %% ways: %% %% 1. \Typo{}{} for typographical corrections, showing original %% %% and replacement text side-by-side. %% %% 2. \Chg{}{} and \Add{}, for inconsistent/missing punctuation %% %% and capitalization. %% %% 3. [** TN: Note]s for lengthier or stylistic comments. %% %% %% %% %% %% Compilation Flags: %% %% %% %% The following behavior may be controlled by boolean flags. %% %% %% %% ForPrinting (false by default): %% %% If false, compile a screen optimized file (one-sided layout, %% %% blue hyperlinks). If true, print-optimized PDF file: Larger %% %% text block, two-sided layout, black hyperlinks. %% %% %% %% %% %% PDF pages: 101(if ForPrinting set to false) %% %% PDF page size: 5.5 x 7.5" (non-standard) %% %% %% %% Summary of log file: %% %% * No warnings %% %% %% %% Compile History: %% %% %% %% July, 2011: (Andrew D. Hwang) %% %% texlive2007, GNU/Linux %% %% %% %% Command block: %% %% %% %% pdflatex x2 %% %% %% %% %% %% July 2011: pglatex. %% %% Compile this project with: %% %% pdflatex 36884-t.tex ..... TWO times %% %% %% %% pdfTeXk, Version 3.141592-1.40.3 (Web2C 7.5.6) %% %% %% %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% \listfiles \documentclass[12pt]{book}[2005/09/16] %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% PACKAGES %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% \usepackage[utf8]{inputenc}[2006/05/05] \usepackage[greek,english]{babel}[2005/11/23] \languageattribute{greek}{polutoniko} \usepackage{ifthen}[2001/05/26] %% Logical conditionals \usepackage{amsmath}[2000/07/18] %% Displayed equations \usepackage{amssymb}[2002/01/22] %% and additional symbols \usepackage{alltt}[1997/06/16] %% boilerplate, credits, license \usepackage{array}[2005/08/23] %% extended array/tabular features \usepackage{indentfirst}[1995/11/23] \usepackage[perpage,symbol]{footmisc}[2005/03/17] \usepackage[labelformat=empty,labelfont=small]{caption}[2007/01/07] \usepackage{calc}[2005/08/06] \usepackage{fancyhdr} %% For running heads %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% %%%% Interlude: Set up PRINTING (default) or SCREEN VIEWING %%%% %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% % ForPrinting=true false (default) % Asymmetric margins Symmetric margins % 1 : 1.62 text block aspect ratio 3 : 4 text block aspect ratio % Black hyperlinks Blue hyperlinks % Start major marker pages recto No blank verso pages % \newboolean{ForPrinting} %% UNCOMMENT the next line for a PRINT-OPTIMIZED VERSION of the text %% %\setboolean{ForPrinting}{true} %% Initialize values to ForPrinting=false \newcommand{\Margins}{hmarginratio=1:1} % Symmetric margins \newcommand{\HLinkColor}{blue} % Hyperlink color \newcommand{\PDFPageLayout}{SinglePage} \newcommand{\TransNote}{Transcriber's Note} \newcommand{\TransNoteCommon}{% The camera-quality files for this public-domain ebook may be downloaded \textit{gratis} at \begin{center} \texttt{book.klll.cc/ebooks/\ebook}. \end{center} This ebook was produced using scanned images and OCR text generously provided by the University of Toronto McLennan Library through the Internet Archive. \bigskip Minor typographical corrections and presentational changes have been made without comment. Punctuation has been regularized, but may be easily reverted to match the original; changes are documented in the \LaTeX\ source file. \bigskip } \newcommand{\TransNoteText}{% \TransNoteCommon This PDF file is optimized for screen viewing, but may be recompiled for printing. Please consult the preamble of the \LaTeX\ source file for instructions and other particulars. } %% Re-set if ForPrinting=true \ifthenelse{\boolean{ForPrinting}}{% \renewcommand{\Margins}{hmarginratio=2:3} % Asymmetric margins \renewcommand{\HLinkColor}{black} % Hyperlink color \renewcommand{\PDFPageLayout}{TwoPageRight} \renewcommand{\TransNote}{Transcriber's Note} \renewcommand{\TransNoteText}{% \TransNoteCommon This PDF file is optimized for printing, but may be recompiled for screen viewing. Please consult the preamble of the \LaTeX\ source file for instructions and other particulars. } }{% If ForPrinting=false, don't skip to recto \renewcommand{\cleardoublepage}{\clearpage} } %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% %%%% End of PRINTING/SCREEN VIEWING code; back to packages %%%% %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% \ifthenelse{\boolean{ForPrinting}}{% \setlength{\paperwidth}{8.5in}% \setlength{\paperheight}{11in}% % ~1:1.67 \usepackage[body={5.25in,8.75in},\Margins]{geometry}[2002/07/08] }{% \setlength{\paperwidth}{5.5in}% \setlength{\paperheight}{7.5in}% \raggedbottom % ~3:4 \usepackage[body={5.25in,6.6in},\Margins,includeheadfoot]{geometry}[2002/07/08] } \providecommand{\ebook}{00000} % Overridden during white-washing \usepackage[pdftex, hyperfootnotes=false, pdftitle={The Project Gutenberg eBook \#\ebook: The Mathematical Analysis of Logic}, pdfauthor={George Boole}, pdfkeywords={University of Toronto, The Internet Archive, Andrew D. Hwang}, pdfstartview=Fit, % default value pdfstartpage=1, % default value pdfpagemode=UseNone, % default value bookmarks=true, % default value linktocpage=false, % default value pdfpagelayout=\PDFPageLayout, pdfdisplaydoctitle, pdfpagelabels=true, bookmarksopen=true, bookmarksopenlevel=0, colorlinks=true, linkcolor=\HLinkColor]{hyperref}[2007/02/07] %% Fixed-width environment to format PG boilerplate %% \newenvironment{PGtext}{% \begin{alltt} %\fontsize{9.2}{11}\ttfamily\selectfont}% \fontsize{10}{12}\ttfamily\selectfont}% {\end{alltt}} % Errors found during digitization \newcommand{\Typo}[2]{#2} % Stylistic changes made for consistency \newcommand{\Chg}[2]{#2} %\newcommand{\Chg}[2]{#1} % Use this to revert inconsistencies in the original \newcommand{\Add}[1]{\Chg{}{#1}} %% Miscellaneous global parameters %% % No hrule in page header \renewcommand{\headrulewidth}{0pt} % Match array row separation to AMS environments \setlength{\extrarowheight}{3pt} % Scratch pad for length calculations \newlength{\TmpLen} %% Running heads %% \newcommand{\FlushRunningHeads}{\clearpage\fancyhf{}} \newcommand{\InitRunningHeads}{% \setlength{\headheight}{15pt} \pagestyle{fancy} \thispagestyle{empty} \ifthenelse{\boolean{ForPrinting}} {\fancyhead[RO,LE]{\thepage}} {\fancyhead[R]{\thepage}} } \newcommand{\SetRunningHeads}[1]{% \fancyhead[C]{\textsc{\MakeLowercase{#1}}} } \newcommand{\BookMark}[2]{\phantomsection\pdfbookmark[#1]{#2}{#2}} %% Major document divisions %% \newcommand{\PGBoilerPlate}{% \pagenumbering{Alph} \pagestyle{empty} \BookMark{0}{PG Boilerplate.} } \newcommand{\FrontMatter}{% \cleardoublepage \frontmatter } \newcommand{\MainMatter}{% \FlushRunningHeads \InitRunningHeads \mainmatter } \newcommand{\PGLicense}{% \FlushRunningHeads \pagenumbering{Roman} \InitRunningHeads \BookMark{0}{PG License.} \SetRunningHeads{License.} } %% Sectional units %% % Typographical abstraction \newcommand{\ChapHead}[1]{% \section*{\centering\normalfont\normalsize\MakeUppercase{#1}} } % To refer internally to chapters by number \newcounter{ChapNo} % Cross-ref: \ChapRef{number}{Title} \newcommand{\ChapRef}[2]{\hyperref[chap:#1]{\textit{#2}}} % \Chapter{Title} \newcommand{\Chapter}[1]{% \FlushRunningHeads \InitRunningHeads \BookMark{0}{#1} \refstepcounter{ChapNo}\label{chap:\theChapNo} \SetRunningHeads{#1} %[** TN: Project-dependent behavior] \ifthenelse{\equal{#1}{Introduction.}}{% \begin{center} \textbf{MATHEMATICAL ANALYSIS OF LOGIC.} \\ \bigskip \tb \end{center} \ChapHead{\MakeUppercase{#1}} }{% \ChapHead{\MakeUppercase{#1}} \begin{center} \tb \end{center} } } \newcommand{\Section}[1]{ \subsection*{\centering\normalsize\normalfont\textit{#1}} } \newcommand{\Signature}[1]{\nopagebreak[4]\bigskip {\small #1} } % Smaller text at the start of four chapters \newenvironment{Abstract}{\small}{\normalsize\medskip} % One-off environment for title page Greek quote \newenvironment{Quote}{\begin{minipage}{\textwidth} \normalfont\hspace*{1.5em} \selectlanguage{greek}}{\end{minipage}} % Italicized theorem-like structure; may start in-line or have a run-in heading \newenvironment{Rule}[1][Rule. ]{% \textsc{#1}\itshape\ignorespaces}{\upshape\par} % Cross-ref-able proposition \newcommand{\Prop}[1]{% \textsc{Prop.~#1}\phantomsection\label{prop:#1}% } \newcommand{\PropRef}[1]{\hyperref[prop:#1.]{Prop.~#1}} \newcommand{\Pagelabel}[1]{\phantomsection\label{page:#1}} \newcommand{\Pageref}[1]{\hyperref[page:#1]{p.~\pageref*{page:#1}}} \newcommand{\Pagerefs}[2]{% \ifthenelse{\equal{\pageref*{page:#1}}{\pageref*{page:#2}}}{% \hyperref[page:#1]{p.~\pageref*{page:#1}}% }{% Else pp.~\hyperref[page:#1]{\pageref*{page:#1}},~\hyperref[page:#2]{\pageref*{page:#2}}% }% } % Page separators \newcommand{\PageSep}[1]{\ignorespaces} % Miscellaneous textual conveniences (N.B. \emph, not \textit) \newcommand{\eg}{\emph{e.\,g.}} \newcommand{\ie}{\emph{i.\,e.}} \newcommand{\etc}{\text{\&c}} \renewcommand{\(}{{\upshape(}} \renewcommand{\)}{{\upshape)}} \newcommand{\First}[1]{\textsc{#1}} % Decorative rule \newcommand{\tb}[1][0.75in]{\rule{#1}{0.5pt}} %% Braces for alignments; smaller than AMS defaults % \Rbrace{2} spans two lines \newcommand{\Rbrace}[1]{% \makebox[8pt][l]{% $\left.\rule[4pt*#1]{0pt}{4pt*#1}\right\}$% }\ } \newcommand{\Lbrace}[1]{% \makebox[4pt][r]{% $\left\{\rule[4pt*#1]{0pt}{4pt*#1}\right.$% }\!\!% } % Small-type column headings for alignments \newcommand{\ColHead}[1]{\text{\footnotesize#1}} %% Miscellaneous mathematical formatting %% \DeclareInputMath{183}{\cdot} %% Selected upright capital letters in math mode \DeclareMathSymbol{A}{\mathalpha}{operators}{`A} \DeclareMathSymbol{B}{\mathalpha}{operators}{`B} \DeclareMathSymbol{C}{\mathalpha}{operators}{`C} \DeclareMathSymbol{D}{\mathalpha}{operators}{`D} \DeclareMathSymbol{E}{\mathalpha}{operators}{`E} \DeclareMathSymbol{I}{\mathalpha}{operators}{`I} \DeclareMathSymbol{O}{\mathalpha}{operators}{`O} \DeclareMathSymbol{V}{\mathalpha}{operators}{`V} \DeclareMathSymbol{W}{\mathalpha}{operators}{`W} \DeclareMathSymbol{X}{\mathalpha}{operators}{`X} \DeclareMathSymbol{Y}{\mathalpha}{operators}{`Y} \DeclareMathSymbol{Z}{\mathalpha}{operators}{`Z} \renewcommand{\epsilon}{\varepsilon} % \PadTo[alignment]{width text}{visible text} \newcommand{\PadTo}[3][c]{% \settowidth{\TmpLen}{$#2$}% \makebox[\TmpLen][#1]{$#3$}% } \newcommand{\PadTxt}[3][c]{% \settowidth{\TmpLen}{#2}% \makebox[\TmpLen][#1]{#3}% } % Cross-ref-able Arabic equation tags... \newcommand{\Tag}[2][eqn]{\phantomsection\label{#1:#2}\tag*{\ensuremath{#2}}} \newcommand{\Eqref}[2][eqn]{\hyperref[#1:#2]{\ensuremath{#2}}} % ...and Greek equation tags \newcommand{\GrTag}[2][]{% \phantomsection\label{eqn:#1} \tag*{\ensuremath{#2}} } \newcommand{\GrEq}[2][]{\hyperref[eqn:#1]{\ensuremath{#2}}} % Boole uses (a) and (b) as "local" tags; no need to cross-ref \newcommand{\atag}{\rlap{\quad$(a)$}} \newcommand{\aref}{$(a)$} \newcommand{\btag}{\rlap{\quad$(b)$}} \newcommand{\bref}{$(b)$} % "Label" tag: Other tag-like labels on displayed equations; no cross-refs \newcommand{\Ltag}[1]{% \ifthenelse{\equal{#1}{I}}{% \tag*{#1\,\qquad} % Pad "I" on the right }{ \tag*{#1\qquad} } } %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% START OF DOCUMENT %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% \begin{document} %% PG BOILERPLATE %% \PGBoilerPlate \begin{center} \begin{minipage}{\textwidth} \small \begin{PGtext} Project Gutenberg's The Mathematical Analysis of Logic, by George Boole This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere at no cost and with almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included with this eBook or online at book.klll.cc Title: The Mathematical Analysis of Logic Being an Essay Towards a Calculus of Deductive Reasoning Author: George Boole Release Date: July 28, 2011 [EBook #36884] Most recently updated: June 11, 2021 Language: English Character set encoding: UTF-8 *** START OF THIS PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK THE MATHEMATICAL ANALYSIS OF LOGIC *** \end{PGtext} \end{minipage} \end{center} \newpage %% Credits and transcriber's note %% \begin{center} \begin{minipage}{\textwidth} \begin{PGtext} Produced by Andrew D. Hwang \end{PGtext} \end{minipage} \vfill \end{center} \begin{minipage}{0.85\textwidth} \small \BookMark{0}{Transcriber's Note.} \subsection*{\centering\normalfont\scshape% \normalsize\MakeLowercase{\TransNote}}% \raggedright \TransNoteText \end{minipage} %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% FRONT MATTER %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% \PageSep{i} \FrontMatter \begin{center} \bfseries\large THE MATHEMATICAL ANALYSIS \vfil \Large OF LOGIC, \vfil \normalsize BEING AN ESSAY TOWARDS A CALCULUS \\ OF DEDUCTIVE REASONING. \vfil BY GEORGE BOOLE. \vfil \begin{Quote} >Epikoinwno~usi d`e p~asai aepist~hmai >all'hlais kat`a t`a koin'a. \Typo{Koin'a}{Koin`a} d`e l'egw, o>~is qr~wntai ek to'utwn >apodeikn'untes; >all'' o>u per`i <~wn deikn'uousin, \Typo{o>ude}{o>ud`e} <`o deikn'uousi. \\ \selectlanguage{english} \null\hfill\textsc{Aristotle}, \textit{Anal.\ Post.}, lib.~\textsc{i}. cap.~\textsc{xi}. \end{Quote} \vfil\vfil CAMBRIDGE: \\ MACMILLAN, BARCLAY, \& MACMILLAN; \\ LONDON: GEORGE BELL. \\ \tb[0.25in] \\ 1847 \normalfont \end{center} \PageSep{ii} \newpage \normalfont \null \vfill \begin{center} \scriptsize PRINTED IN ENGLAND BY \\ HENDERSON \& SPALDING \\ LONDON. W.I \end{center} \PageSep{1} \MainMatter \Chapter{Preface.} \First{In} presenting this Work to public notice, I deem it not irrelevant to observe, that speculations similar to those which it records have, at different periods, occupied my thoughts. In the spring of the present year my attention was directed to the question then moved between Sir W.~Hamilton and Professor De~Morgan; and I was induced by the interest which it inspired, to resume the almost-forgotten thread of former inquiries. It appeared to me that, although Logic might be viewed with reference to the idea of quantity,\footnote {See \Pageref{42}.} it had also another and a deeper system of relations. If it was lawful to regard it from \emph{without}, as connecting itself through the medium of Number with the intuitions of Space and Time, it was lawful also to regard it from \emph{within}, as based upon facts of another order which have their abode in the constitution of the Mind. The results of this view, and of the inquiries which it suggested, are embodied in the following Treatise. It is not generally permitted to an Author to prescribe the mode in which his production shall be judged; but there are two conditions which I may venture to require of those who shall undertake to estimate the merits of this performance. The first is, that no preconceived notion of the impossibility of its objects shall be permitted to interfere with that candour and impartiality which the investigation of Truth demands; the second is, that their judgment of the system as a whole shall not be founded either upon the examination of only \PageSep{2} a part of it, or upon the measure of its conformity with any received system, considered as a standard of reference from which appeal is denied. It is in the general theorems which occupy the latter chapters of this work,---results to which there is no existing counterpart,---that the claims of the method, as a Calculus of Deductive Reasoning, are most fully set forth. What may be the final estimate of the value of the system, I have neither the wish nor the right to anticipate. The estimation of a theory is not simply determined by its truth\Add{.} It also depends upon the importance of its subject, and the extent of its applications; beyond which something must still be left to the arbitrariness of human Opinion. If the utility of the application of Mathematical forms to the science of Logic were solely a question of Notation, I should be content to rest the defence of this attempt upon a principle which has been stated by an able living writer: ``Whenever the nature of the subject permits the reasoning process to be without danger carried on mechanically, the language should be constructed on as mechanical principles as possible; while in the contrary case it should be so constructed, that there shall be the greatest possible obstacle to a mere mechanical use of it.''\footnote {Mill's \textit{System of Logic, Ratiocinative and Inductive}, Vol.~\textsc{ii}. p.~292.} In one respect, the science of Logic differs from all others; the perfection of its method is chiefly valuable as an evidence of the speculative truth of its principles. To supersede the employment of common reason, or to subject it to the rigour of technical forms, would be the last desire of one who knows the value of that intellectual toil and warfare which imparts to the mind an athletic vigour, and teaches it to contend with difficulties and to rely upon itself in emergencies. \Signature{\textsc{Lincoln}, \textit{Oct.}~29, 1847.} \PageSep{3} %[**TN: Macro prints heading "MATHEMATICAL ANALYSIS OF LOGIC."] \Chapter{Introduction.} \First{They} who are acquainted with the present state of the theory of Symbolical Algebra, are aware, that the validity of the processes of analysis does not depend upon the interpretation of the symbols which are employed, but solely upon the laws of their combination. Every system of interpretation which does not affect the truth of the relations supposed, is equally admissible, and it is thus that the same process may, under one scheme of interpretation, represent the solution of a question on the properties of numbers, under another, that of a geometrical problem, and under a third, that of a problem of dynamics or optics. This principle is indeed of fundamental importance; and it may with safety be affirmed, that the recent advances of pure analysis have been much assisted by the influence which it has exerted in directing the current of investigation. But the full recognition of the consequences of this important doctrine has been, in some measure, retarded by accidental circumstances. It has happened in every known form of analysis, that the elements to be determined have been conceived as measurable by comparison with some fixed standard. The predominant idea has been that of magnitude, or more strictly, of numerical ratio. The expression of magnitude, or \PageSep{4} of operations upon magnitude, has been the express object for which the symbols of Analysis have been invented, and for which their laws have been investigated. Thus the abstractions of the modern Analysis, not less than the ostensive diagrams of the ancient Geometry, have encouraged the notion, that Mathematics are essentially, as well as actually, the Science of Magnitude. The consideration of that view which has already been stated, as embodying the true principle of the Algebra of Symbols, would, however, lead us to infer that this conclusion is by no means necessary. If every existing interpretation is shewn to involve the idea of magnitude, it is only by induction that we can assert that no other interpretation is possible. And it may be doubted whether our experience is sufficient to render such an induction legitimate. The history of pure Analysis is, it may be said, too recent to permit us to set limits to the extent of its applications. Should we grant to the inference a high degree of probability, we might still, and with reason, maintain the sufficiency of the definition to which the principle already stated would lead us. We might justly assign it as the definitive character of a true Calculus, that it is a method resting upon the employment of Symbols, whose laws of combination are known and general, and whose results admit of a consistent interpretation. That to the existing forms of Analysis a quantitative interpretation is assigned, is the result of the circumstances by which those forms were determined, and is not to be construed into a universal condition of Analysis. It is upon the foundation of this general principle, that I purpose to establish the Calculus of Logic, and that I claim for it a place among the acknowledged forms of Mathematical Analysis, regardless that in its object and in its instruments it must at present stand alone. That which renders Logic possible, is the existence in our minds of general notions,---our ability to conceive of a class, and to designate its individual members by a common name. \PageSep{5} \Pagelabel{5}% The theory of Logic is thus intimately connected with that of Language. A successful attempt to express logical propositions by symbols, the laws of whose combinations should be founded upon the laws of the mental processes which they represent, would, so far, be a step toward a philosophical language. But this is a view which we need not here follow into detail.\footnote {This view is well expressed in one of Blanco White's Letters:---``Logic is for the most part a collection of technical rules founded on classification. The Syllogism is nothing but a result of the classification of things, which the mind naturally and necessarily forms, in forming a language. All abstract terms are classifications; or rather the labels of the classes which the mind has settled.''---\textit{Memoirs of the Rev.\ Joseph Blanco White}, vol.~\textsc{ii}. p.~163. See also, for a very lucid introduction, Dr.~Latham's \textit{First Outlines of Logic applied to Language}, Becker's \textit{German Grammar,~\etc.} Extreme Nominalists make Logic entirely dependent upon language. For the opposite view, see Cudworth's \textit{Eternal and Immutable Morality}, Book~\textsc{iv}. Chap.~\textsc{iii}.} Assuming the notion of a class, we are able, from any conceivable collection of objects, to separate by a mental act, those which belong to the given class, and to contemplate them apart from the rest. Such, or a similar act of election, we may conceive to be repeated. The group of individuals left under consideration may be still further limited, by mentally selecting those among them which belong to some other recognised class, as well as to the one before contemplated. And this process may be repeated with other elements of distinction, until we arrive at an individual possessing all the distinctive characters which we have taken into account, and a member, at the same time, of every class which we have enumerated. It is in fact a method similar to this which we employ whenever, in common language, we accumulate descriptive epithets for the sake of more precise definition. Now the several mental operations which in the above case we have supposed to be performed, are subject to peculiar laws. It is possible to assign relations among them, whether as respects the repetition of a given operation or the succession of different ones, or some other particular, which are never violated. It is, for example, true that the result of two successive acts is \PageSep{6} unaffected by the order in which they are performed; and there are at least two other laws which will be pointed out in the proper place. These will perhaps to some appear so obvious as to be ranked among necessary truths, and so little important as to be undeserving of special notice. And probably they are noticed for the first time in this Essay. Yet it may with confidence be asserted, that if they were other than they are, the entire mechanism of reasoning, nay the very laws and constitution of the human intellect, would be vitally changed. A Logic might indeed exist, but it would no longer be the Logic we possess. Such are the elementary laws upon the existence of which, and upon their capability of exact symbolical expression, the method of the following Essay is founded; and it is presumed that the object which it seeks to attain will be thought to have been very fully accomplished. Every logical proposition, whether categorical or hypothetical, will be found to be capable of exact and rigorous expression, and not only will the laws of conversion and of syllogism be thence deducible, but the resolution of the most complex systems of propositions, the separation of any proposed element, and the expression of its value in terms of the remaining elements, with every subsidiary relation involved. Every process will represent deduction, every mathematical consequence will express a logical inference. The generality of the method will even permit us to express arbitrary operations of the intellect, and thus lead to the demonstration of general theorems in logic analogous, in no slight degree, to the general theorems of ordinary mathematics. No inconsiderable part of the pleasure which we derive from the application of analysis to the interpretation of external nature, arises from the conceptions which it enables us to form of the universality of the dominion of law. The general formulæ to which we are conducted seem to give to that element a visible presence, and the multitude of particular cases to which they apply, demonstrate the extent of its sway. Even the symmetry \PageSep{7} of their analytical expression may in no fanciful sense be deemed indicative of its harmony and its consistency. Now I do not presume to say to what extent the same sources of pleasure are opened in the following Essay. The measure of that extent may be left to the estimate of those who shall think the subject worthy of their study. But I may venture to assert that such occasions of intellectual gratification are not here wanting. The laws we have to examine are the laws of one of the most important of our mental faculties. The mathematics we have to construct are the mathematics of the human intellect. Nor are the form and character of the method, apart from all regard to its interpretation, undeserving of notice. There is even a remarkable exemplification, in its general theorems, of that species of excellence which consists in freedom from exception. And this is observed where, in the corresponding cases of the received mathematics, such a character is by no means apparent. The few who think that there is that in analysis which renders it deserving of attention for its own sake, may find it worth while to study it under a form in which every equation can be solved and every solution interpreted. Nor will it lessen the interest of this study to reflect that every peculiarity which they will notice in the form of the Calculus represents a corresponding feature in the constitution of their own minds. It would be premature to speak of the value which this method may possess as an instrument of scientific investigation. I speak here with reference to the theory of reasoning, and to the principle of a true classification of the forms and cases of Logic considered as a Science.\footnote {``Strictly a Science''; also ``an Art.''---\textit{Whately's Elements of Logic.} Indeed ought we not to regard all Art as applied Science; unless we are willing, with ``the multitude,'' to consider Art as ``guessing and aiming well''?---\textit{Plato, Philebus.}} The aim of these investigations was in the first instance confined to the expression of the received logic, and to the forms of the Aristotelian arrangement, \PageSep{8} but it soon became apparent that restrictions were thus introduced, which were purely arbitrary and had no foundation in the nature of things. These were noted as they occurred, and will be discussed in the proper place. When it became necessary to consider the subject of hypothetical propositions (in which comparatively less has been done), and still more, when an interpretation was demanded for the general theorems of the Calculus, it was found to be imperative to dismiss all regard for precedent and authority, and to interrogate the method itself for an expression of the just limits of its application. Still, however, there was no special effort to arrive at novel results. But among those which at the time of their discovery appeared to be such, it may be proper to notice the following. A logical proposition is, according to the method of this Essay, expressible by an equation the form of which determines the rules of conversion and of transformation, to which the given proposition is subject. Thus the law of what logicians term simple conversion, is determined by the fact, that the corresponding equations are symmetrical, that they are unaffected by a mutual change of place, in those symbols which correspond to the convertible classes. The received laws of conversion were thus determined, and afterwards another system, which is thought to be more elementary, and more general. See Chapter, \ChapRef{5}{On the Conversion of Propositions}. The premises of a syllogism being expressed by equations, the elimination of a common symbol between them leads to a third equation which expresses the conclusion, this conclusion being always the most general possible, whether Aristotelian or not. Among the cases in which no inference was possible, it was found, that there were two distinct forms of the final equation. It was a considerable time before the explanation of this fact was discovered, but it was at length seen to depend upon the presence or absence of a true medium of comparison between the premises. The distinction which is thought to be new is illustrated in the Chapter, \ChapRef{6}{On Syllogisms}. \PageSep{9} The nonexclusive character of the disjunctive conclusion of a hypothetical syllogism, is very clearly pointed out in the examples of this species of argument. The class of logical problems illustrated in the chapter, \ChapRef{9}{On the Solution of Elective Equations}, is conceived to be new: and it is believed that the method of that chapter affords the means of a perfect analysis of any conceivable system of propositions, an end toward which the rules for the conversion of a single categorical proposition are but the first step. However, upon the originality of these or any of these views, I am conscious that I possess too slight an acquaintance with the literature of logical science, and especially with its older literature, to permit me to speak with confidence. It may not be inappropriate, before concluding these observations, to offer a few remarks upon the general question of the use of symbolical language in the mathematics. Objections have lately been very strongly urged against this practice, on the ground, that by obviating the necessity of thought, and substituting a reference to general formulæ in the room of personal effort, it tends to weaken the reasoning faculties. Now the question of the use of symbols may be considered in two distinct points of view. First, it may be considered with reference to the progress of scientific discovery, and secondly, with reference to its bearing upon the discipline of the intellect. And with respect to the first view, it may be observed that as it is one fruit of an accomplished labour, that it sets us at liberty to engage in more arduous toils, so it is a necessary result of an advanced state of science, that we are permitted, and even called upon, to proceed to higher problems, than those which we before contemplated. The practical inference is obvious. If through the advancing power of scientific methods, we find that the pursuits on which we were once engaged, afford no longer a sufficiently ample field for intellectual effort, the remedy is, to proceed to higher inquiries, and, in new tracks, to seek for difficulties yet unsubdued. And such is, \PageSep{10} indeed, the actual law of scientific progress. We must be content, either to abandon the hope of further conquest, or to employ such aids of symbolical language, as are proper to the stage of progress, at which we have arrived. Nor need we fear to commit ourselves to such a course. We have not yet arrived so near to the boundaries of possible knowledge, as to suggest the apprehension, that scope will fail for the exercise of the inventive faculties. In discussing the second, and scarcely less momentous question of the influence of the use of symbols upon the discipline of the intellect, an important distinction ought to be made. It is of most material consequence, whether those symbols are used with a full understanding of their meaning, with a perfect comprehension of that which renders their use lawful, and an ability to expand the abbreviated forms of reasoning which they induce, into their full syllogistic \Typo{devolopment}{development}; or whether they are mere unsuggestive characters, the use of which is suffered to rest upon authority. The answer which must be given to the question proposed, will differ according as the one or the other of these suppositions is admitted. In the former case an intellectual discipline of a high order is provided, an exercise not only of reason, but of the faculty of generalization. In the latter case there is no mental discipline whatever. It were perhaps the best security against the danger of an unreasoning reliance upon symbols, on the one hand, and a neglect of their just claims on the other, that each subject of applied mathematics should be treated in the spirit of the methods which were known at the time when the application was made, but in the best form which those methods have assumed. The order of attainment in the individual mind would thus bear some relation to the actual order of scientific discovery, and the more abstract methods of the higher analysis would be offered to such minds only, as were prepared to receive them. The relation in which this Essay stands at once to Logic and \PageSep{11} to Mathematics, may further justify some notice of the question which has lately been revived, as to the relative value of the two studies in a liberal education. One of the chief objections which have been urged against the study of Mathematics in general, is but another form of that which has been already considered with respect to the use of symbols in particular. And it need not here be further dwelt upon, than to notice, that if it avails anything, it applies with an equal force against the study of Logic. The canonical forms of the Aristotelian syllogism are really symbolical; only the symbols are less perfect of their kind than those of mathematics. If they are employed to test the validity of an argument, they as truly supersede the exercise of reason, as does a reference to a formula of analysis. Whether men do, in the present day, make this use of the Aristotelian canons, except as a special illustration of the rules of Logic, may be doubted; yet it cannot be questioned that when the authority of Aristotle was dominant in the schools of Europe, such applications were habitually made. And our argument only requires the admission, that the case is possible. But the question before us has been argued upon higher grounds. Regarding Logic as a branch of Philosophy, and defining Philosophy as the ``science of a real existence,'' and ``the research of causes,'' and assigning as its \emph{main} business the investigation of the ``why, (\textgreek{t`o d'ioti}),'' while Mathematics display only the ``that, (\textgreek{t`o {\qquad}rr@{\,}c@{\,}l@{}} &y(1 - x) &=& 0\Add{,} \\ &vz &=& vy\Add{,} \\ \cline{2-4} &vz(1 - x) &=& 0\Add{,} \\ \therefore\ & \multicolumn{3}{l}{\rlap{Some~$Z$s are~$X$s.}} \end{array} \] Ex.~2. $AO$, Fig.~2, and, by mutation, $OA$, Fig.~2. \[ \begin{alignedat}[t]{2} &\text{All~$X$s are~$Y$s,}\qquad& x(1 - y) &= 0, \\ &\text{Some~$Z$s are not~$Y$s,} & vz &= v(1 - y), \end{alignedat}\quad \begin{array}[t]{rr@{\,}c@{\,}l@{}} &x &=& xy\Add{,} \\ &vy &=& v(1 - z)\Add{,} \\ \cline{2-4} &vx &=& vx(1 - z)\Add{,} \\ &vxz&=& 0\Add{,} \\ \multicolumn{4}{r}{\llap{$\therefore\ \text{Some~$Z$s are not~$X$s.}$}} \end{array} \] The interpretation of~$vz$ as Some~$Z$s, is implied, it will be observed, in the equation $vz = v(1 - y)$ considered as representing the proposition Some~$Z$s are not~$Y$s. The cases not determinable by the Aristotelian Rules are $OE$, Fig.~1, and, by mutation, $EO$, Fig.~4. \[ \begin{aligned}[t] &\text{Some~$Y$s are not~$X$s,} \\ &\text{No~$Z$s are~$Y$s,} \end{aligned}\qquad \begin{array}[t]{>{\qquad}rr@{\,}c@{\,}l@{}} &vy &=& v(1 - x)\Add{,} \\ & 0 &=& zy\Add{,} \\ \cline{2-4} & 0 &=& v(1 - x)z\Add{,} \\ \multicolumn{4}{c}{\makebox[0pt][c]{$\therefore$\ Some not-$X$s are not~$Z$s.}} \end{array} \] The equation of the first premiss here permits us to interpret $v(1 - x)$, but it does not enable us to interpret~$vz$. \PageSep{38} Of cases in which no inference is possible, we take as examples--- $AO$, Fig.~1, and, by mutation, $OA$, Fig.~4\Typo{,}{.} \[ \begin{alignedat}[t]{2} &\text{All~$Y$s are~$X$s,}\qquad& y(1 - x) &= 0, \\ &\text{Some~$Z$s are not~$Y$s,} & vz &= v(1 - y)\Add{,}\atag \end{alignedat}\qquad \begin{array}[t]{r@{\,}c@{\,}l@{}} y(1 - x) &=& 0\Add{,} \\ v(1 - z) &=& vy\Add{,} \\ \cline{1-3} v(1 - z)(1 - x) &=& 0\Add{,}\btag \\ 0&=& 0\Add{,} \end{array} \] since the auxiliary equation in this case is $v(1 - z) = 0$. Practically it is not necessary to perform this reduction, but it is satisfactory to do so. The equation~\aref, it is seen, defines~$vz$ as Some~$Z$s, but it does not define $v(1 - z)$, so that we might stop at the result of elimination~\bref, and content ourselves with saying, that it is not interpretable into a relation between the classes $X$~and~$Z$. Take as a second example $AI$, Fig.~2, and, by mutation, $IA$, Fig.~2\Typo{,}{.} \[ \begin{alignedat}[t]{2} &\text{All~$X$s are~$Y$s,}\qquad& x(1 - y) &= 0, \\ &\text{Some~$Z$s are~$Y$s,} & vz &= vy, \end{alignedat}\qquad \begin{array}[t]{r@{\,}c@{\,}l@{}} x &=& xy\Add{,} \\ vy &=& vz\Add{,} \\ \cline{1-3} vx &=& vxz\Add{,} \\ \llap{$v(1 - z)x$}&=& 0\Add{,} \\ 0&=& 0, \end{array} \] the auxiliary equation in this case being $v(1 - z)= 0$. Indeed in every case in this class, in which no inference is possible, the result of elimination is reducible to the form $0 = 0$. Examples therefore need not be multiplied. \textsc{Class} 4th.---When $v$~enters into both equations. No inference is possible in any case, but there exists a distinction among the unlawful cases which is peculiar to this class. The two divisions are, 1st. When the result of elimination is reducible by the auxiliary equations to the form $0 = 0$. The cases are $II$, $OI$, \PageSep{39} Fig.~1; $II$, $OO$, Fig.~2; $II$, $IO$, $OI$, $OO$, Fig.~3; $II$, $IO$, Fig.~4. 2nd. When the result of elimination is not reducible by the auxiliary equations to the form $0 = 0$. The cases are $IO$, $OO$, Fig.~1; $IO$, $OI$, Fig.~2; $OI$, $OO$, Fig.~4. Let us take as an example of the former case,~$II$, Fig.~3. \[ \begin{alignedat}[t]{2} &\text{Some~$X$s are~$Y$s,}\qquad& vx &= vy, \\ &\text{Some~$Z$s are~$Y$s,} & v'z &= v'y, \end{alignedat}\qquad \begin{array}[t]{r@{\,}c@{\,}l@{}} vx &=& vy\Add{,} \\ v'y &=& v'z\Add{,} \\ \cline{1-3} vv'x &=& vv'z\Add{.} \end{array} \] Now the auxiliary equations $v(1 - x) = 0$, $v'(1 - z) = 0$, %[** TN: Next word anomalously displayed in the original] give \[ vx = v,\quad v'z = v'. \] Substituting we have \begin{align*} vv' &= vv', \\ \therefore 0 &= 0. \end{align*} As an example of the latter case, let us take $IO$, Fig.~1\Typo{,}{.} \[ \begin{alignedat}[t]{2} &\text{Some~$Y$s are~$X$s,} & vy &= vx, \\ &\text{Some~$Z$s are not~$Y$s,}\qquad& v'z &= v'(1 - y), \end{alignedat}\quad \begin{array}[t]{r@{\,}c@{\,}l@{}} vy &=& vx\Add{,} \\ v'(1 - z) &=& v'y\Add{,} \\ \cline{1-3} vv'(1 - z) &=& vv'x\Add{.} \end{array} \] Now the auxiliary equations being $v(1 - x) = 0$, $v'(1 - z) = 0$, the above reduces to $vv' = 0$. It is to this form that all similar cases are reducible. Its interpretation is, that the classes $v$ and~$v'$ have no common member, as is indeed evident. The above classification is purely founded on mathematical distinctions. We shall now inquire what is the logical division to which it corresponds. The lawful cases of the first class comprehend all those in which, from two universal premises, a universal conclusion may be drawn. We see that they include the premises of \textit{barbara} and \textit{celarent} in the first figure, of \textit{cesare} and \textit{camestres} in the second, and of \textit{bramantip} and \textit{camenes} in the fourth. \PageSep{40} The premises of \textit{bramantip} are included, because they admit of an universal conclusion, although not in the same figure. The lawful cases of the second class are those in which a particular conclusion only is deducible from two universal premises. The lawful cases of the third class are those in which a conclusion is deducible from two premises, one of which is universal and the other particular. The fourth class has no lawful cases. Among the cases in which no inference of any kind is possible, we find six in the fourth class distinguishable from the others by the circumstance, that the result of elimination does not assume the form $0 = 0$. The cases are {\small \[ \Lbrace{2}\begin{aligned} &\text{Some~$Y$s are~$X$s,} \\ &\text{Some~$Z$s are not~$Y$s,} \end{aligned}\Rbrace{2}\quad % \Lbrace{2}\begin{aligned} &\text{Some~$Y$s are not~$X$s,} \\ &\text{Some~$Z$s are not~$Y$s,} \end{aligned}\Rbrace{2}\quad % \Lbrace{2}\begin{aligned} &\text{Some~$X$s are~$Y$s,} \\ &\text{Some~$Z$s are not~$Y$s,} \end{aligned}\Rbrace{2} \] }% and the three others which are obtained by mutation of premises. It might be presumed that some logical peculiarity would be found to answer to the mathematical peculiarity which we have noticed, and in fact there exists a very remarkable one. If we examine each pair of premises in the above scheme, we shall find that there \emph{is virtually} no middle term, \emph{\ie~no medium of comparison}, in any of them. Thus, in the first example, the individuals spoken of in the first premiss are asserted to belong to the class~$Y$, but those spoken of in the second premiss are \emph{virtually} asserted to belong to the class not-$Y$: nor can we by any lawful transformation or conversion alter this state of things. The comparison will still be made with the class~$Y$ in one premiss, and with the class not-$Y$ in the other. Now in every case beside the above six, there will be found a middle term, either expressed or implied. I select two of the most difficult cases. \PageSep{41} In $AO$, Fig.~1, viz. \begin{align*} &\text{All~$Y$s are~$X$s,} \\ &\text{Some~$Z$s are not~$Y$s,} \end{align*} we have, by \emph{negative conversion} of the first premiss, \begin{align*} &\text{All not-$X$s are not-$Y$s,} \\ &\text{Some~$Z$s are not~$Y$s,} \end{align*} and the middle term is now seen to be not-$Y$. Again, in $EO$, Fig.~1, \begin{align*} &\text{No~$Y$s are~$X$s,} \\ &\text{Some~$Z$s are not~$Y$s,} \end{align*} a proved conversion of the first premiss (see \ChapRef{5}{Conversion of Propositions}), gives \begin{align*} &\text{All~$X$s are not-$Y$s,} \\ &\text{Some~$Z$s are not-$Y$s,} \end{align*} and the middle term, the true medium of comparison, is plainly \Pagelabel{41}% not-$Y$, although as the not-$Y$s in the one premiss \emph{may be} different from those in the other, no conclusion can be drawn. The mathematical condition in question, therefore,---the irreducibility of the final equation to the form $0 = 0$,---adequately represents the logical condition of there being no middle term, or common medium of comparison, in the given premises. I am not aware that the distinction occasioned by the presence or absence of a middle term, in the strict sense here understood, has been noticed by logicians before. The distinction, though real and deserving attention, is indeed by no means an obvious one, and it would have been unnoticed in the present instance but for the peculiarity of its mathematical expression. What appears to be novel in the above case is the proof of the existence of combinations of premises in which there \PageSep{42} is absolutely no medium of comparison. When such a medium of comparison, or true middle term, does exist, the condition that its quantification in both premises together shall exceed its quantification as a single whole, has been ably and \Pagelabel{42}% clearly shewn by Professor De~Morgan to be necessary to lawful inference (\textit{Cambridge Memoirs}, Vol.~\textsc{viii}.\ Part~3). And this is undoubtedly the true principle of the Syllogism, viewed from the standing-point of Arithmetic. I have said that it would be possible to impose conditions of interpretation which should restrict the results of this calculus to the Aristotelian forms. Those conditions would be, 1st. That we should agree not to interpret the forms $v(1 - x)$, $v(1 - z)$. 2ndly. That we should agree to reject every interpretation in which the order of the terms should violate the Aristotelian rule. Or, instead of the second condition, it might be agreed that, the conclusion being determined, the order of the premises should, if necessary, be changed, so as to make the syllogism formal. From the \emph{general} character of the system it is indeed plain, that it may be made to represent any conceivable scheme of logic, by imposing the conditions proper to the case contemplated. We have found it, in a certain class of cases, to be necessary to replace the two equations expressive of universal Propositions, by their solutions; and it may be proper to remark, that it would have been allowable in all instances to have done this,\footnote {It may be satisfactory to illustrate this statement by an example. In \textit{\Chg{Barbara}{barbara}}, we should have \[ \begin{aligned}[t] &\text{All~$Y$s are~$X$s,} \\ &\text{All~$Z$s are~$Y$s,} \end{aligned}\qquad \begin{array}[t]{>{\qquad}r@{\,}c@{\,}l@{}} y &=& vx\Add{,} \\ z &=& v'y\Add{,} \\ \cline{1-3} z &=& vv'x\Add{,} \\ \multicolumn{3}{c}{\makebox[0pt][c]{$\therefore$\ All~$Z$s are~$X$s.}} \end{array} \] %[** TN: Footnote continues] Or, we may multiply the resulting equation by~$1 - x$, which gives \[ z(1 - x) = 0, \] whence the same conclusion, All~$Z$s are~$X$s. Some additional examples of the application of the system of equations in the text to the demonstration of general theorems, may not be inappropriate. Let $y$ be the term to be eliminated, and let $x$ stand indifferently for either of the other symbols, then each of the equations of the premises of any given syllogism may be put in the form \[ ay + bx = 0, \GrTag[a]{(\alpha)} \] if the premiss is affirmative, and in the form \[ ay + b(1 - x) = 0, \GrTag[b]{(\beta)} \] if it is negative, $a$~and~$b$ being either constant, or of the form~$±v$. To prove this in detail, let us examine each kind of proposition, making $y$~successively subject and predicate. \begin{alignat*}{2} A,\ &\text{All~$Y$s are~$X$s,} & y - vx &= 0, \GrTag[c]{(\gamma)} \\ &\text{All~$X$s are~$Y$s,} & x - vy &= 0, \GrTag[d]{(\delta)} \\ % E,\ &\text{No~$Y$s are~$X$s,} & xy &= 0, \\ &\text{No~$X$s are~$Y$s,} & y - v(1 - x) &= 0, \GrTag[e]{(\epsilon)} \\ % I,\ &\text{Some~$X$s are~$Y$s,} && \\ &\text{Some~$Y$s are~$X$s,} &vx - vy &= 0, \GrTag[f]{(\zeta)} \\ % O,\ &\text{Some~$Y$s are not~$X$s,}\qquad& vy - v(1 - x) &= 0, \GrTag[g]{(\eta)} \\ &\text{Some~$X$s are not~$Y$s,} & vx &= v(1 - y), \\ && \therefore vy - v(1 - x) &= 0. \GrTag[h]{(\theta)} \end{alignat*} The affirmative equations \GrEq[c]{(\gamma)},~\GrEq[d]{(\delta)} and~\GrEq[f]{(\zeta)}, belong to~\GrEq[a]{(\alpha)}, and the negative equations \GrEq[e]{(\epsilon)},~\GrEq[g]{(\eta)} and~\GrEq[h]{(\theta)}, to~\GrEq[b]{(\beta)}. It is seen that the two last negative equations are alike, but there is a difference of interpretation. In the former \[ v(1 - x) = \text{Some not-$X$s,} \] in the latter, \[ v(1 - x) = 0. \] The utility of the two general forms of reference, \GrEq[a]{(\alpha)}~and~\GrEq[b]{(\beta)}, will appear from the following application. 1st. \emph{A conclusion drawn from two affirmative propositions} is itself affirmative. By \GrEq[a]{(\alpha)} we have for the given propositions, \begin{alignat*}{2} ay &+ bx &&= 0, \\ a'y &+ b'z &&= 0, \end{alignat*} %[** TN: Footnote continues] and eliminating \[ ab'z - a'bx = 0, \] which is of the form~\GrEq[a]{(\alpha)}. Hence, if there is a conclusion, it is affirmative. 2nd. \emph{A conclusion drawn from an affirmative and a negative proposition is negative.} By \GrEq[a]{(\alpha)}~and~\GrEq[b]{(\beta)}, we have for the given propositions \begin{align*} ay + bx &= 0, \\ a'y + b'(1 - z) &= 0, \\ \therefore\ a'bx - ab'(1 - z) &= 0, \end{align*} which is of the form~\GrEq[b]{(\beta)}. Hence the conclusion, if there is one, is negative. 3rd. \emph{A conclusion drawn from two negative premises will involve a negation, \(not-$X$, not-$Z$\) in both subject and predicate, and will therefore be inadmissible in the Aristotelian system, though just in itself.} For the premises being \begin{alignat*}{2} ay &+ b (1 - x) &&= 0, \\ a'y &+ b'(1 - z) &&= 0, \end{alignat*} the conclusion will be \[ ab'(1 - z) - a'b(1 - x) = 0, \] which is only interpretable into a proposition that has a negation in each term. 4th. \emph{Taking into account those syllogisms only, in which the conclusion is the most general, that can be deduced from the premises,---if, in an Aristotelian syllogism, the minor premises be changed in quality \(from affirmative to negative or from negative to affirmative\), whether it be changed in quantity or not, no conclusion will be deducible in the same figure.} An Aristotelian proposition does not admit a term of the form not-$Z$ in the subject,---Now on changing the quantity of the minor proposition of a syllogism, we transfer it from the general form \begin{align*} ay + bz &= 0, \\ \intertext{to the general form} a'y + b'(1 - z) &= 0, \end{align*} see \GrEq[a]{(\alpha)}~\emph{and}~\GrEq[b]{(\beta)}, or \textit{vice versâ}. And therefore, in the equation of the conclusion, there will be a change from~$z$ to~$1 - z$, or \textit{vice versâ}. But this is equivalent to the change of~$Z$ into not-$Z$, or not-$Z$ into~$Z$. Now the subject of the original conclusion must have involved a~$Z$ and not a not-$Z$, therefore the subject of the new conclusion will involve a not-$Z$, and the conclusion will not be admissible in the Aristotelian forms, except by conversion, which would render necessary a change of Figure. Now the conclusions of this calculus are always the most general that can be drawn, and therefore the above demonstration must not be supposed to extend to a syllogism, in which a particular conclusion is deduced, when a universal one is possible. This is the case with \textit{bramantip} only, among the Aristotelian forms, and therefore the transformation of \textit{bramantip} into \textit{camenes}, and \textit{vice versâ}, is the case of restriction contemplated in the preliminary statement of the theorem. 5th. \emph{If for the minor premiss of an Aristotelian syllogism, we substitute its contradictory, no conclusion is deducible in the same figure.} It is here only necessary to examine the case of \textit{bramantip}, all the others being determined by the last proposition. On changing the minor of \textit{bramantip} to its contradictory, we have $AO$, Fig.~4, and this admits of no legitimate inference. Hence the theorem is true without exception. Many other general theorems may in like manner be proved.} %[** TN: End of 3.5-page footnote] so that every case of the Syllogism, without exception, \PageSep{43} might have been treated by equations comprised in the general forms \Pagelabel{43}% \begin{alignat*}{3} y &= vx, &&\text{or} & y - vx &= 0, \Ltag{A} \\ y &= v(1 - x),\qquad&&\text{or}\quad & y + vx - v &= 0, \Ltag{E} \\ vy &= vx, &&& vy - vx &= 0, \Ltag{I} \\ vy &= v(1 - x), &&& vy + vx - v &= 0. \Ltag{O} \end{alignat*} \PageSep{44} Perhaps the system we have actually employed is better, as distinguishing the cases in which $v$~only \emph{may} be employed, \PageSep{45} from those in which it \emph{must}. But for the demonstration of certain general properties of the Syllogism, the above system is, from its simplicity, and from the mutual analogy of its forms, very convenient. We shall apply it to the following theorem.\footnote {This elegant theorem was communicated by the Rev.\ Charles Graves, Fellow and Professor of Mathematics in Trinity College, Dublin, to whom the Author desires further to record his grateful acknowledgments for a very judicious examination of the former portion of this work, and for some new applications of the method. The following example of Reduction \textit{ad~impossibile} is among the number: \[ \begin{array}{rl<{\quad}r@{\,}c@{\,}l@{}} \text{Reducend Mood,} & \text{All~$X$s are~$Y$s,} & 1 - y &=& v'(1 - x)\Add{,} \\ \PadTxt{Reducend Mood,}{\textit{\Chg{Baroko}{baroko}}} & \text{Some~$Z$s are not~$Y$s\Add{,}} & vz &=& v(1 - y)\Add{,} \\ \cline{3-5} % &\text{Some~$Z$s are not~$X$s\Add{,}} & vz &=& vv'(1 - x)\Add{,} \\ % \text{Reduct Mood,} & \text{All~$X$s are~$Y$s\Add{,}} & 1 - y &=& v'(1 - x)\Add{,} \\ \PadTxt{Reduct Mood,}{\textit{\Chg{Barbara}{barbara}}} & \text{All~$Z$s are~$X$s\Add{,}} & z(1 - x) &=& 0\Add{,} \\ \cline{2-5} &\text{All~$Z$s are~$Y$s\Add{,}} & z(1 - y) &=& 0. \end{array} \] The conclusion of the reduct mood is seen to be the contradictory of the suppressed minor premiss. Whence,~\etc. It may just be remarked that the mathematical test of contradictory propositions is, that on eliminating one elective symbol between their equations, the other elective symbol vanishes. The \emph{ostensive} reduction of \textit{\Chg{Baroko}{baroko}} and \textit{\Chg{Bokardo}{bokardo}} involves no difficulty. Professor Graves suggests the employment of the equation $x = vy$ for the primary expression of the Proposition All~$X$s are~$Y$s, and remarks, that on multiplying both members by~$1 - y$, we obtain $x(1 - y) = 0$, the equation from which we set out in the text, and of which the previous one is a solution.} Given the three propositions of a Syllogism, prove that there is but one order in which they can be legitimately arranged, and determine that order. All the forms above given for the expression of propositions, are particular cases of the general form, \[ a + bx + cy = 0. \] \PageSep{46} Assume then for the premises of the given syllogism, the equations \begin{alignat*}{3} a &+ bx &&+ cy &&= 0, \Tag{(18)} \\ a' &+ b'z &&+ c'y &&= 0, \Tag{(19)} \end{alignat*} then, eliminating~$y$, we shall have for the conclusion \[ ac' - a'c + bc'x - b'cz = 0. \Tag{(20)} \] Now taking this as one of our premises, and either of the original equations, suppose~\Eqref{(18)}, as the other, if by elimination of a common term~$x$, between them, we can obtain a result equivalent to the remaining premiss~\Eqref{(19)}, it will appear that there are more than one order in which the Propositions may be lawfully written; but if otherwise, one arrangement only is lawful. Effecting then the elimination, we have \[ bc(a' + b'z + c'y) = 0, \Tag{(21)} \] which is equivalent to~\Eqref{(19)} multiplied by a factor~$bc$. Now on examining the value of this factor in the equations $A$,~$E$, $I$,~$O$, we find it in each case to be $v$~or~$-v$. But it is evident, that if an equation expressing a given Proposition be multiplied by an extraneous factor, derived from another equation, its interpretation will either be limited or rendered impossible. Thus there will either be no result at all, or the result will be a \emph{limitation} of the remaining Proposition. If, however, one of the original equations were \[ x = y,\quad\text{or}\quad x - y = 0, \] the factor~$bc$ would be~$-1$, and would \emph{not} limit the interpretation of the other premiss. Hence if the first member of a syllogism should be understood to represent the double proposition All~$X$s are~$Y$s, and All~$Y$s are~$X$s, it would be indifferent in what order the remaining Propositions were written. \PageSep{47} A more general form of the above investigation would be, to express the premises by the equations \begin{alignat*}{4} a &+ bx &&+ cy &&+ dxy &&= 0, \Tag{(22)} \\ a' &+ b'z &&+ c'y &&+ d'zy &&= 0. \Tag{(23)} \end{alignat*} After the double elimination of $y$~and~$x$ we should find \[ (bc - ad)(a' + b'z + c'y + d'zy) = 0; \] and it would be seen that the factor $bc - ad$ must in every case either vanish or express a limitation of meaning. The determination of the order of the Propositions is sufficiently obvious. \PageSep{48} \Chapter{Of Hypotheticals.} \begin{Abstract} A hypothetical Proposition is defined to be \emph{two or more categoricals united by a copula} (or conjunction), and the different kinds of hypothetical Propositions are named from their respective conjunctions, viz.\ conditional (if), disjunctive (either, or),~\etc. In conditionals, that categorical Proposition from which the other results is called the \emph{antecedent}, that which results from it the \emph{consequent}. Of the conditional syllogism there are two, and only two formulæ. 1st. The constructive, \begin{gather*} \text{If $A$~is~$B$, then $C$~is~$D$,} \\ \text{But $A$~is~$B$, therefore $C$~is~$D$.} \end{gather*} 2nd. The Destructive, \begin{gather*} \text{If $A$~is~$B$, then $C$~is~$D$,} \\ \text{But $C$~is not~$D$, therefore $A$~is not~$B$.} \end{gather*} A dilemma is a complex conditional syllogism, with several antecedents in the major, and a disjunctive minor. \end{Abstract} \First{If} we examine either of the forms of conditional syllogism above given, we shall see that the validity of the argument does not depend upon any considerations which have reference to the terms $A$,~$B$,~$C$,~$D$, considered as the representatives of individuals or of classes. We may, in fact, represent the Propositions $A$~is~$B$, $C$~is~$D$, by the arbitrary symbols $X$~and~$Y$ respectively, and express our syllogisms in such forms as the following: \begin{gather*} \text{If $X$ is true, then $Y$ is true,} \\ \text{But $X$ is true, therefore $Y$ is true.} \end{gather*} Thus, what we have to consider is not objects and classes of objects, but the truths of Propositions, namely, of those \PageSep{49} elementary Propositions which are embodied in the terms of our hypothetical premises. To the symbols $X$,~$Y$,~$Z$, representative of Propositions, we may appropriate the elective symbols $x$,~$y$,~$z$, in the following sense. The hypothetical Universe,~$1$, shall comprehend all conceivable cases and conjunctures of circumstances. The elective symbol~$x$ attached to any subject expressive of such cases shall select those cases in which the Proposition~$X$ is true, and similarly for $Y$~and~$Z$. If we confine ourselves to the contemplation of a given proposition~$X$, and hold in abeyance every other consideration, then two cases only are conceivable, viz.\ first that the given Proposition is true, and secondly that it is false.\footnote {It was upon the obvious principle that a Proposition is either true or false, that the Stoics, applying it to assertions respecting future events, endeavoured to establish the doctrine of Fate. It has been replied to their argument, that it %[** TN: Italicized entire Latin phrase; only "est" italicized in original] involves ``an abuse of the word \emph{true}, the precise meaning of which is \textit{id quod res est}. An assertion respecting the future is neither true nor false.''---\textit{Copleston on Necessity and Predestination}, p.~36. Were the Stoic axiom, however, presented under the form, It is either certain that a given event will take place, or certain that it will not; the above reply would fail to meet the difficulty. The proper answer would be, that no merely verbal definition can settle the question, what is the actual course and constitution of Nature. When we affirm that it is either certain that an event will take place, or certain that it will not take place, we tacitly assume that the order of events is necessary, that the Future is but an evolution of the Present; so that the state of things which is, completely determines that which shall be. But this (at least as respects the conduct of moral agents) is the very question at issue. Exhibited under its proper form, the Stoic reasoning does not involve an abuse of terms, but a \textit{petitio principii}. It should be added, that enlightened advocates of the doctrine of Necessity in the present day, viewing the end as appointed only in and through the means, justly repudiate those practical ill consequences which are the reproach of Fatalism.} As these cases together make up the Universe of the Proposition, and as the former is determined by the elective symbol~$x$, the latter is determined by the symbol~$1 - x$. But if other considerations are admitted, each of these cases will be resolvable into others, individually less extensive, the \PageSep{50} number of which will depend upon the number of foreign considerations admitted. Thus if we associate the Propositions $X$ and~$Y$, the total number of conceivable cases will be found as exhibited in the following scheme. \[ \begin{array}[b]{*{2}{l@{\ }}>{\qquad}c@{}} \multicolumn{2}{c}{\ColHead{Cases.}} & \multicolumn{1}{>{\qquad}c}{\ColHead{Elective expressions.}} \\ \text{1st}& \text{$X$ true, $Y$ true\Add{,}} & xy\Add{,} \\ \text{2nd}& \text{$X$ true, $Y$ false\Add{,}}& x(1 - y)\Add{,} \\ \text{3rd}& \text{$X$ false, $Y$ true\Add{,}} & (1 - x)y\Add{,} \\ \text{4th}& \text{$X$ false, $Y$ false\Add{,}}& (1 - x)(1 - y)\Add{.} \end{array} \Tag{(24)} \] If we add the elective expressions for the two first of the above cases the sum is~$x$, which is the elective symbol appropriate to the more general case of $X$~being true independently of any consideration of~$Y$; and if we add the elective expressions in the two last cases together, the result is~$1 - x$, which is the elective expression appropriate to the more general case of $X$~being false. Thus the extent of the hypothetical Universe does not at all depend upon the number of circumstances which are taken into account. And it is to be noted that however few or many those circumstances may be, the sum of the elective expressions representing every conceivable case will be unity. Thus let us consider the three Propositions, $X$,~It rains, $Y$,~It hails, $Z$,~It freezes. The possible cases are the following: \[ \begin{array}{*{2}{l@{\ }}l@{}} &\multicolumn{1}{c}{\ColHead{Cases.}} & \multicolumn{1}{c}{\ColHead{Elective expressions.}} \\ \text{1st}& \text{It rains, hails, and freezes,} & xyz\Add{,} \\ \text{2nd}& \text{It rains and hails, but does not freeze\Add{,}}& xy(1 - z)\Add{,} \\ \text{3rd}& \text{It rains and freezes, but does not hail\Add{,}}& xz(1 - y)\Add{,} \\ \text{4th}& \text{It freezes and hails, but does not rain\Add{,}}& yz(1 - x)\Add{,} \\ \text{5th}& \text{It rains, but neither hails nor freezes\Add{,}}& x(1 - y)(1 - z)\Add{,} \\ \text{6th}& \text{It hails, but neither rains nor freezes\Add{,}}& y(1 - x)(1 - z)\Add{,} \\ \text{7th}& \text{It freezes, but neither hails nor rains\Add{,}}& z(1 - x)(1 - y)\Add{,} \\ \text{8th}& \text{It neither rains, hails, nor freezes\Add{,}}& (1 - x)(1 - y)(1 - z)\Add{,} \\ \cline{3-3} &&\multicolumn{1}{c}{1 = \text{sum\Add{.}}} \end{array} \] \PageSep{51} \Section{Expression of Hypothetical Propositions.} To express that a given Proposition~$X$ is true. The symbol $1 - x$ selects those cases in which the Proposition~$X$ is false. But if the Proposition is true, there are no such cases in its hypothetical Universe, therefore \begin{align*} 1 - x &= 0, \\ \intertext{or} x &= 1. \Tag{(25)} \end{align*} To express that a given Proposition~$X$ is false. The elective symbol~$x$ selects all those cases in which the Proposition is true, and therefore if the Proposition is false, \[ x = 0. \Tag{(26)} \] And in every case, having determined the elective expression appropriate to a given Proposition, we assert the truth of that Proposition by equating the elective expression to unity, and its falsehood by equating the same expression to~$0$. To express that two Propositions, $X$~and~$Y$, are simultaneously true. The elective symbol appropriate to this case is~$xy$, therefore the equation sought is \[ xy = 1. \Tag{(27)} \] To express that two Propositions, $X$~and~$Y$, are simultaneously false. The condition will obviously be \begin{align*} (1 - x)(1 - y) &= 1, \\ \intertext{or} x + y - xy &= 0. \Tag{(28)} \end{align*} To express that either the Proposition~$X$ is true, or the Proposition~$Y$ is true. To assert that either one or the other of two Propositions is true, is to assert that it is not true, that they are both false. Now the elective expression appropriate to their both being false is~$(1 - x)(1 - y)$, therefore the equation required is \begin{align*} (1 - x)(1 - y) &= 0, \\ \intertext{or} x + y - xy &= 1. \Tag{(29)} \end{align*} \PageSep{52} And, by indirect considerations of this kind, may every disjunctive Proposition, however numerous its members, be expressed. But the following general Rule will usually be preferable. \begin{Rule} Consider what are those distinct and mutually exclusive cases of which it is implied in the statement of the given Proposition, that some one of them is true, and equate the sum of their elective expressions to unity. This will give the equation of the given Proposition. \end{Rule} For the sum of the elective expressions for all distinct conceivable cases will be unity. Now all these cases being mutually exclusive, and it being asserted in the given Proposition that some one case out of a given set of them is true, it follows that all which are not included in that set are false, and that their elective expressions are severally equal to~$0$. Hence the sum of the elective expressions for the remaining cases, viz.\ those included in the given set, will be unity. Some one of those cases will therefore be true, and as they are mutually exclusive, it is impossible that more than one should be true. Whence the Rule in question. And in the application of this Rule it is to be observed, that if the cases contemplated in the given disjunctive Proposition are not mutually exclusive, they must be resolved into an equivalent series of cases which are mutually exclusive. Thus, if we take the Proposition of the preceding example, viz.\ Either $X$~is true, or $Y$~is true, and assume that the two members of this Proposition are not exclusive, insomuch that in the enumeration of possible cases, we must reckon that of the Propositions $X$~and~$Y$ being both true, then the mutually exclusive cases which fill up the Universe of the Proposition, with their elective expressions, are \[ \begin{array}{l@{\ }l<{\qquad}c@{}} \text{1st,}& \text{$X$~true and $Y$~false,}& x(1 - y), \\ \text{2nd,}& \text{$Y$~true and $X$~false,}& y(1 - x), \\ \text{3rd,}& \text{$X$~true and $Y$~true,} & xy, \end{array} \] \PageSep{53} and the sum of these elective expressions equated to unity gives \[ x + y - xy = 1\Typo{.}{,} \Tag{(30)} \] as before. But if we suppose the members of the disjunctive Proposition to be exclusive, then the only cases to be considered are \[ \begin{array}{l@{\ }l<{\qquad}c@{}} \text{1st,}& \text{$X$~true, $Y$~false,}& x(1 - y), \\ \text{2nd,}& \text{$Y$~true, $X$~false,}& y(1 - x), \end{array} \] and the sum of these elective expressions equated to~$0$, gives \[ x - 2xy + y = 1. \Tag{(31)} \] The subjoined examples will further illustrate this method. To express the Proposition, Either $X$~is not true, or $Y$~is not true, the members being exclusive. The mutually exclusive cases are \[ \begin{array}{l@{\ }l<{\qquad}c@{}} \text{1st,}& \text{$X$~not true, $Y$~true,}& y(1 - x), \\ \text{2nd,}& \text{$Y$~not true, $X$~true,}& x(1 - y), \end{array} \] and the sum of these equated to unity gives \[ x - 2xy + y = 1, \Tag{(32)} \] which is the same as~\Eqref{(31)}, and in fact the Propositions which they represent are equivalent. To express the Proposition, Either $X$~is not true, or $Y$~is not true, the members not being exclusive. To the cases contemplated in the last Example, we must add the following, viz. \[ \text{$X$~not true, $Y$~not true,}\qquad (1 - x)(1 - y). \] The sum of the elective expressions gives \begin{gather*} x(1 - y) + y(1 - x) + (1 - x)(1 - y) = 1, \\ \intertext{or} xy = 0. \Tag{(33)} \end{gather*} To express the disjunctive Proposition, Either $X$~is true, or $Y$~is true, or $Z$~is true, the members being exclusive. \PageSep{54} Here the mutually exclusive cases are \[ \begin{array}{l@{\ }l<{\qquad}c@{}} \text{1st,}& \text{$X$~true, $Y$~false, $Z$~false,}& x(1 - y)(1 - z), \\ \text{2nd,}& \text{$Y$~true, $Z$~false, $X$~false,}& y(1 - z)(1 - x), \\ \text{3rd,}& \text{$Z$~true, $X$~false, $Y$~false,}& z(1 - x)(1 - y), \end{array} \] and the sum of the elective expressions equated to~$1$, gives, upon reduction, \[ x + y + z - 2(xy + yz + zx) + 3xyz = 1. \Tag{(34)} \] The expression of the same Proposition, when the members are in no sense exclusive, will be \[ (1 - x)(1 - y)(1 - z) = 0. \Tag{(35)} \] And it is easy to see that our method will apply to the expression of any similar Proposition, whose members are subject to any specified amount and character of exclusion. To express the conditional Proposition, If $X$~is true, $Y$~is true. Here it is implied that all the cases of $X$~being true, are cases of $Y$~being true. The former cases being determined by the elective symbol~$x$, and the latter by~$y$, we have, in virtue of~\Eqref{(4)}, \[ x(1 - y) = 0. \Tag{(36)} \] To express the conditional Proposition, If $X$~be true, $Y$~is not true. The equation is obviously \[ xy = 0; \Tag{(37)} \] this is equivalent to~\Eqref{(33)}, and in fact the disjunctive Proposition, Either $X$~is not true, or $Y$~is not true, and the conditional Proposition, If $X$~is true, $Y$~is not true, are equivalent. To express that If $X$~is not true, $Y$~is not true. In~\Eqref{(36)} write $1 - x$ for~$x$, and $1 - y$ for~$y$, we have \[ (1 - x)y = 0. \] \PageSep{55} The results which we have obtained admit of verification in many different ways. Let it suffice to take for more particular examination the equation \[ x - 2xy + y = 1, \Tag{(38)} \] which expresses the conditional Proposition, Either $X$~is true, or $Y$~is true, the members being in this case exclusive. First, let the Proposition~$X$ be true, then $x = 1$, and substituting, we have \[ 1 - 2y + y = 1,\qquad \therefore -y = 0,\quad\text{or}\quad y = 0, \] which implies that $Y$~is not true. Secondly, let $X$~be not true, then $x = 0$, and the equation gives \[ y = 1, \Tag{(39)} \] which implies that $Y$~is true. In like manner we may proceed with the assumptions that $Y$~is true, or that $Y$~is false. Again, in virtue of the property $x^{2} = x$, $y^{2} = y$, we may write the equation in the form \[ x^{2} - 2xy + y^{2} = 1, \] and extracting the square root, we have \[ x - y = ±1, \Tag{(40)} \] and this represents the actual case; for, as when $X$~is true or false, $Y$~is respectively false or true, we have \begin{gather*} x = 1\quad\text{or}\quad 0, \\ y = 0\quad\text{or}\quad 1, \\ \therefore x - y = 1\quad\text{or}\quad -1. \end{gather*} There will be no difficulty in the analysis of other cases. \Section{Examples of Hypothetical Syllogism.} The treatment of every form of hypothetical Syllogism will consist in forming the equations of the premises, and eliminating the symbol or symbols which are found in more than one of them. The result will express the conclusion. \PageSep{56} 1st. Disjunctive Syllogism. \begin{align*} &\begin{array}{l<{\qquad}@{}c@{}} \text{Either $X$~is true, or $Y$~is true (exclusive),} & x + y - 2xy = 1\Add{,} \\ \text{But $X$~is true,} & x = 1\Add{,} \\ \cline{2-2} \text{Therefore $Y$~is not true,} & \therefore y = 0\Add{.} \end{array} \\ &\begin{array}{l<{\quad}@{}c@{}} \text{Either $X$~is true, or $Y$~is true (not exclusive),}& x + y - xy = 1\Add{,} \\ \text{But $X$~is not true,}& x = 0\Add{,} \\ \cline{2-2} \text{Therefore $Y$~is true,}& \therefore y = 1\Add{.} \end{array} \end{align*} 2nd. Constructive Conditional Syllogism. \[ \begin{array}{l<{\qquad}@{}c@{}} \text{If $X$~is true, $Y$~is true,}& x(1 - y) = 0\Add{,} \\ \text{But $X$~is true,}& x = 1\Add{,} \\ \text{Therefore $Y$~is true,}& \therefore 1 - y = 0\quad\text{or}\quad y = 1. \end{array} \] 3rd. Destructive Conditional Syllogism. \[ \begin{array}{l<{\qquad}@{}r@{}} \text{If $X$~is true, $Y$~is true,}& x(1 - y) = 0\Add{,} \\ \text{But $Y$~is not true,}& y = 0\Add{,} \\ \text{Therefore $X$~is not true,}& \therefore x = 0\Add{.} \end{array} \] 4th. Simple Constructive Dilemma, the minor premiss exclusive. \begin{alignat*}{2} &\text{If $X$~is true, $Y$~is true,}& x(1 - y) &= 0, \Tag{(41)} \\ &\text{If $Z$~is true, $Y$~is true,}& z(1 - y) &= 0, \Tag{(42)} \\ &\text{But Either $X$~is true, or $Z$~is true,}\quad& x + z - 2xz &= 1. \Tag{(43)} \end{alignat*} From the equations \Eqref{(41)},~\Eqref{(42)},~\Eqref{(43)}, we have to eliminate $x$~and~$z$. In whatever way we effect this, the result is \[ y = 1; \] whence it appears that the Proposition~$Y$ is true. 5th. Complex Constructive Dilemma, the minor premiss not exclusive. \[ \begin{array}{l<{\qquad}@{}r@{}} \text{If $X$~is true, $Y$~is true,}& x(1 - y) = 0, \\ \text{If $W$~is true, $Z$~is true,}& w(1 - z) = 0, \\ \text{Either $X$~is true, or $W$~is true,}& x + w - xw = 1. \end{array} \] From these equations, eliminating~$x$, we have \[ y + z - yz = 1, \] \PageSep{57} which expresses the Conclusion, Either $Y$~is true, or $Z$~is true, the members being \Chg{non-exclusive}{nonexclusive}. 6th. Complex Destructive Dilemma, the minor premiss exclusive. \[ \begin{array}{l<{\qquad}@{}r@{}} \text{If $X$~is true, $Y$~is true,}& x(1 - y) = 0\Add{,} \\ \text{If $W$~is true, $Z$~is true,}& w(1 - z) = 0\Add{,} \\ \text{Either $Y$~is not true, or $Z$~is not true,}& y + z - 2yz = 1. \end{array} \] From these equations we must eliminate $y$~and~$z$. The result is \[ xw = 0, \] which expresses the Conclusion, Either $X$~is not true, or $Y$~is not true, the members \emph{not being exclusive}. 7th. Complex Destructive Dilemma, the minor premiss not exclusive. \[ \begin{array}{l<{\qquad}@{}r@{}} \text{If $X$~is true, $Y$~is true,}& x(1 - y) = 0\Add{,} \\ \text{If $W$~is true, $Z$~is true,}& w(1 - z) = 0\Add{,} \\ \text{Either $Y$~is not true, or $Z$~is not true,}& yz = 0. \end{array} \] On elimination of $y$~and~$z$, we have \[ xw = 0, \] which indicates the same Conclusion as the previous example. It appears from these and similar cases, that whether the members of the minor premiss of a Dilemma are exclusive or not, the members of the (disjunctive) Conclusion are never exclusive. This fact has perhaps escaped the notice of logicians. The above are the principal forms of hypothetical Syllogism which logicians have recognised. It would be easy, however, to extend the list, especially by the blending of the disjunctive and the conditional character in the same Proposition, of which the following is an example. \[ \begin{array}{l<{\qquad}@{}c@{}} \multicolumn{2}{l}{% \text{If $X$~is true, then either $Y$~is true, or $Z$~is true,}} \\ & x(1 - y - z + yz) = 0\Add{,} \\ \text{But $Y$~is not true,}& y = 0\Add{,} \\ \text{Therefore If $X$~is true, $Z$~is true,}& \therefore x(1 - z) = 0. \end{array} \] \PageSep{58} That which logicians term a \emph{Causal} Proposition is properly a conditional Syllogism, the major premiss of which is suppressed. The assertion that the Proposition~$X$ is true, \emph{because} the Proposition~$Y$ is true, is equivalent to the assertion, \begin{align*} &\text{The Proposition~$Y$ is true,} \\ &\text{\emph{Therefore} the Proposition X is true;} \end{align*} and these are the minor premiss and conclusion of the conditional Syllogism, \begin{align*} &\text{If $Y$~is true, $X$~is true,} \\ &\text{But $Y$~is true,} \\ &\text{Therefore $X$~is true.} \end{align*} And thus causal Propositions are seen to be included in the applications of our general method. Note, that there is a family of disjunctive and conditional Propositions, which do not, of right, belong to the class considered in this Chapter. Such are those in which the force of the disjunctive or conditional particle is expended upon the predicate of the Proposition, as if, speaking of the inhabitants of a particular island, we should say, that they are all \emph{either Europeans or Asiatics}; meaning, that it is true of each individual, that he is either a European or an Asiatic. If we appropriate the elective symbol~$x$ to the inhabitants, $y$~to Europeans, and $z$~to Asiatics, then the equation of the above Proposition is \[ x = xy + xz,\quad\text{or}\quad x(1 - y - z) = 0;\atag \] to which we might add the condition $yz = 0$, since no Europeans are Asiatics. The nature of the symbols $x$,~$y$,~$z$, indicates that the Proposition belongs to those which we have before designated as \emph{Categorical}. Very different from the above is the Proposition, Either all the inhabitants are Europeans, or they are all Asiatics. Here the disjunctive particle separates Propositions. The case is that contemplated in~\Eqref{(31)} of the present Chapter; and the symbols by which it is expressed, \PageSep{59} although subject to the same laws as those of~\aref, have a totally different interpretation.\footnote {Some writers, among whom is Dr.\ Latham (\textit{First Outlines}), regard it as the exclusive office of a conjunction to connect \emph{Propositions}, not \emph{words}. In this view I am not able to agree. The Proposition, Every animal is \emph{either} rational \emph{or} irrational, cannot be resolved into, \emph{Either} every animal is rational, \emph{or} every animal is irrational. The former belongs to pure categoricals, the latter to hypotheticals. In \emph{singular} Propositions, such conversions would seem to be allowable. This animal is \emph{either} rational \emph{or} irrational, is equivalent to, \emph{Either} this animal is rational, \emph{or} it is irrational. This peculiarity of \emph{singular} Propositions would almost justify our ranking them, though truly universals, in a separate class, as Ramus and his followers did.} The distinction is real and important. Every Proposition which language can express may be represented by elective symbols, and the laws of combination of those symbols are in all cases the same; but in one class of instances the symbols have reference to collections of objects, in the other, to the truths of constituent Propositions. \PageSep{60} \Chapter{Properties of Elective Functions.} \First{Since} elective symbols combine according to the laws of quantity, we may, by Maclaurin's theorem, expand a given function~$\phi(x)$, in ascending powers of~$x$, known cases of failure excepted. Thus we have \[ \phi(x) = \phi(0) + \phi'(0)x + \frac{\phi''(0)}{1·2}x^{2} + \etc. \Tag{(44)} \] Now $x^{2} = x$, $x^{3} = x$,~\etc., whence \[ \phi(x) = \phi(0) + x\bigl\{\phi'(0) + \frac{\phi''(0)}{1·2} + \etc.\bigr\}. \Tag{(45)} \] Now if in~\Eqref{(44)} we make $x = 1$, we have \[ \phi(1) = \phi(0) + \phi'(0) + \frac{\phi''(0)}{1·2} + \etc., \] whence \[ \phi'(0) + \frac{\phi''(0)}{1·2} + \frac{\phi'''(0)}{1·2·3} + \etc. = \phi(1) - \phi(0). \] Substitute this value for the coefficient of~$x$ in the second member of~\Eqref{(45)}, and we have\footnote {Although this and the following theorems have only been proved for those forms of functions which are expansible by Maclaurin's theorem, they may be regarded as true for all forms whatever; this will appear from the applications. The reason seems to be that, as it is only through the one form of expansion that elective functions become interpretable, no conflicting interpretation is possible. The development of~$\phi(x)$ may also be determined thus. By the known formula for expansion in factorials, \[ \phi(x) = \phi(0) + \Delta\phi(0)x + \frac{\Delta^{2}\phi(0)}{1·2}x(x - 1) + \etc. \] %[** TN: Footnote continues] Now $x$~being an elective symbol, $x(x - 1) = 0$, so that all the terms after the second, vanish. Also $\Delta\phi(0) = \phi(1) - \phi(0)$, whence \[ \phi\bigl\{x = \phi(0)\bigr\} + \bigl\{\phi(1) - \phi(0)\bigr\}x. \] The mathematician may be interested in the remark, that this is not the only case in which an expansion stops at the second term. The expansions of the compound operative functions $\phi\left(\dfrac{d}{dx} + x^{-1}\right)$ and $\phi\left\{x + \left(\dfrac{d}{dx}\right)^{-1}\right\}$ are, respectively, \[ \phi\left(\frac{d}{dx}\right) + \phi'\left(\frac{d}{dx}\right)x^{-1}, \] and \[ \phi(x) + \phi'(x)\left(\frac{d}{dx}\right)^{-1}. \] See \textit{Cambridge Mathematical Journal}, Vol.~\textsc{iv}. p.~219.} \[ \phi(x) = \phi(0) + \bigl\{\phi(1) - \phi(0)\bigr\}x, \Tag{(46)} \] \PageSep{61} which we shall also employ under the form \[ \phi(x) = \phi(1)x + \phi(0)(1 - x). \Tag{(47)} \] Every function of~$x$, in which integer powers of that symbol are alone involved, is by this theorem reducible to the first order. The quantities $\phi(0)$,~$\phi(1)$, we shall call the moduli of the function~$\phi(x)$. They are of great importance in the theory of elective functions, as will appear from the succeeding Propositions. \Prop{1.} Any two functions $\phi(x)$,~$\psi(x)$, are equivalent, whose corresponding moduli are equal. This is a plain consequence of the last Proposition. For since \begin{align*} \phi(x) &= \phi(0) + \bigl\{\phi(1) - \phi(0)\bigr\}x, \\ \psi(x) &= \psi(0) + \bigl\{\psi(1) - \psi(0)\bigr\}x, \end{align*} it is evident that if $\phi(0) = \psi(0)$, $\phi(1) = \psi(1)$, the two expansions will be equivalent, and therefore the functions which they represent will be equivalent also. The converse of this Proposition is equally true, viz. If two functions are equivalent, their corresponding moduli are equal. Among the most important applications of the above theorem, we may notice the following. Suppose it required to determine for what forms of the function~$\phi(x)$, the following equation is satisfied, viz. \[ \bigl\{\phi(x)\bigr\}^{n} = \phi(x). \] \PageSep{62} Here we at once obtain for the expression of the conditions in question, \[ \bigl\{\phi(0)\bigr\}^{n} = \phi(0)\Typo{.}{,}\quad \bigl\{\phi(1)\bigr\}^{n} = \phi(1). \Tag{(48)} \] Again, suppose it required to determine the conditions under which the following equation is satisfied, viz. \[ \phi(x)\psi(x) = \chi(x)\Typo{,}{.} \] The general theorem at once gives \[ \phi(0)\psi(0) = \chi(0)\Typo{.}{,}\quad \phi(1)\psi(1) = \chi(1). \Tag{(49)} \] This result may also be proved by substituting for~$\phi(x)$, $\psi(x)$, $\chi(x)$, their expanded forms, and equating the coefficients of the resulting equation properly reduced. All the above theorems may be extended to functions of more than one symbol. For, as different elective symbols combine with each other according to the same laws as symbols of quantity, we can first expand a given function with reference to any particular symbol which it contains, and then expand the result with reference to any other symbol, and so on in succession, the order of the expansions being quite indifferent. Thus the given function being~$\phi(xy)$ we have \[ \phi(xy) = \phi(x0) + \bigl\{\phi(x1) - \phi(x0)\bigr\}y, \] and expanding the coefficients with reference to~$x$, and reducing \begin{align*} \phi(xy) = \phi(00) &+ \bigl\{\phi(10) - \phi(00)\bigr\}x + \bigl\{\phi(01) - \phi(00)\bigr\}y \\ &+ \bigl\{\phi(11) - \phi(10) - \phi(01) + \phi(00)\bigr\}xy, \Tag{(50)} \end{align*} to which we may give the elegant symmetrical form \begin{align*} %[** TN: Not aligned in the original] \phi(xy) = \phi(00)(1 - x)(1 - y) &+ \phi(01)y(1 - x) \\ &+ \phi(10)x(1 - y) + \phi(11)xy, \Tag{(51)} \end{align*} wherein we shall, in accordance with the language already employed, designate $\phi(00)$, $\phi(01)$, $\phi(10)$, $\phi(11)$, as the moduli of the function~$\phi(xy)$. By inspection of the above general form, it will appear that any functions of two variables are equivalent, whose corresponding moduli are all equal. \PageSep{63} Thus the conditions upon which depends the satisfaction of the equation, \[ \bigl\{\phi(xy)\bigr\}^{n} = \phi(xy) \] are seen to be \[ \begin{alignedat}{2} \bigl\{\phi(00)\bigr\}^{n} &= \phi(00),\qquad& \bigl\{\phi(01)\bigr\}^{n} &= \phi(01), \\ \bigl\{\phi(10)\bigr\}^{n} &= \phi(10), & \bigl\{\phi(11)\bigr\}^{n} &= \phi(11). \end{alignedat} \Tag{(52)} \] And the conditions upon which depends the satisfaction of the equation \[ \phi(xy)\psi(xy) = \chi(xy), \] are \[ \begin{alignedat}{2} \phi(00)\psi(00) &= \chi(00),\qquad& \phi(01)\psi(01) &= \chi(01), \\ \phi(10)\psi(10) &= \chi(10),\qquad& \phi(11)\psi(11) &= \chi(11). \end{alignedat} \Tag{(53)} \] It is very easy to assign by induction from \Eqref{(47)}~and~\Eqref{(51)}, the general form of an expanded elective function. It is evident that if the number of elective symbols is~$m$, the number of the moduli will be~$2^{m}$, and that their separate values will be obtained by interchanging in every possible way the values $1$~and~$0$ in the places of the elective symbols of the given function. The several terms of the expansion of which the moduli serve as coefficients, will then be formed by writing for each~$1$ that recurs under the functional sign, the elective symbol~$x$,~\etc., which it represents, and for each~$0$ the corresponding~$1 - x$,~\etc., and regarding these as factors, the product of which, multiplied by the modulus from which they are obtained, constitutes a term of the expansion. Thus, if we represent the moduli of any elective function $\phi(xy\dots)$ by $a_{1}$,~$a_{2}$, $\dots,~a_{r}$, the function itself, when expanded and arranged with reference to the moduli, will assume the form \[ \phi(xy) = a_{1}t_{1} + a_{2}t_{2} \dots + a_{r}t_{r}, \Tag{(54)} \] in which $t_{1}t_{2}\dots t_{r}$ are functions of $x$,~$y$,~$\dots$, resolved into factors of the forms $x$,~$y$,~$\dots$ $1 - x$, $1 - y$,~$\dots$~\etc. These functions satisfy individually the index relations \[ t_{1}^{n} = t_{1},\quad t_{2}^{n} = t_{2},\quad \etc., \Tag{(55)} \] and the further relations, \[ t_{1}t_{2} = 0\dots t_{1}t_{2} = 0,~\etc., \Tag{(56)} \] \PageSep{64} the product of any two of them vanishing. This will at once be inferred from inspection of the particular forms \Eqref{(47)}~and~\Eqref{(51)}. Thus in the latter we have for the values of $t_{1}$,~$t_{2}$,~\etc., the forms \[ xy,\quad x(1 - y),\quad (1 - x)y,\quad (1 - x)(1 - y); \] and it is evident that these satisfy the index relation, and that their products all vanish. We shall designate $t_{1}t_{2}\dots$ as the constituent functions of~$\phi(xy)$, and we shall define the peculiarity of the vanishing of the binary products, by saying that those functions are \emph{exclusive}. And indeed the classes which they represent are mutually exclusive. The sum of all the constituents of an expanded function is unity. An elegant proof of this Proposition will be obtained by expanding~$1$ as a function of any proposed elective symbols. Thus if in~\Eqref{(51)} we assume $\phi(xy) = 1$, we have $\phi(11) = 1$, $\phi(10) = 1$, $\phi(01) = 1$, $\phi(00) = 1$, and \Eqref{(51)}~gives \[ 1 = xy + x(1 - y) + (1 - x)y + (1 - x)(1 - y). \Tag{(57)} \] It is obvious indeed, that however numerous the symbols involved, all the moduli of unity are unity, whence the sum of the constituents is unity. We are now prepared to enter upon the question of the general interpretation of elective equations. For this purpose we shall find the following Propositions of the greatest service. \Prop{2.} If the first member of the general equation $\phi(xy\dots) = 0$, be expanded in a series of terms, each of which is of the form~$at$, $a$~being a modulus of the given function, then for every numerical modulus~$a$ which does not vanish, we shall have the equation \[ at = 0, \] and the combined interpretations of these several equations will express the full significance of the original equation. For, representing the equation under the form \[ a_{1}t_{1} + a_{2}t_{2} \dots + a_{r}t_{r} = 0. \Tag{(58)} \] Multiplying by~$t_{1}$ we have, by~\Eqref{(56)}, \[ a_{1}t_{1} = 0, \Tag{(59)} \] \PageSep{65} whence if $a_{1}$~is a numerical constant which does not vanish, \[ t_{1} = 0, \] and similarly for all the moduli which do not vanish. And inasmuch as from these constituent equations we can form the given equation, their interpretations will together express its entire significance. Thus if the given equation were \[ x - y = 0,\quad \text{$X$s~and~$Y$s are identical,} \Tag{(60)} \] we should have $\phi(11) = 0$, $\phi(10) = 1$, $\phi(01) = -1$, $\phi(00) = 0$, so that the expansion~\Eqref{(51)} would assume the form \[ x(1 - y) - y(1 - x) = 0, \] whence, by the above theorem, \begin{alignat*}{2} x(1 - y) &= 0,\qquad& \text{All~$X$s are~$Y$s,} \\ y(1 - x) &= 0, & \text{All~$Y$s are~$X$s,} \end{alignat*} results which are together equivalent to~\Eqref{(60)}. It may happen that the simultaneous satisfaction of equations thus deduced, may require that one or more of the elective symbols should vanish. This would only imply the nonexistence of a class: it may even happen that it may lead to a final result of the form \[ 1 = 0, \] which would indicate the nonexistence of the logical Universe. Such cases will only arise when we attempt to unite contradictory Propositions in a single equation. The manner in which the difficulty seems to be evaded in the result is characteristic. It appears from this Proposition, that the differences in the interpretation of elective functions depend solely upon the number and position of the vanishing moduli. No change in the value of a modulus, but one which causes it to vanish, produces any change in the interpretation of the equation in which it is found. If among the infinite number of different values which we are thus permitted to give to the moduli which do not vanish in a proposed equation, any one value should be \PageSep{66} preferred, it is unity, for when the moduli of a function are all either $0$~or~$1$, the function itself satisfies the condition \[ \bigl\{\phi(xy\dots)\bigr\}^{n} = \phi(xy\dots), \] and this at once introduces symmetry into our Calculus, and provides us with fixed standards for reference. \Prop{3.} If $w = \phi(xy\dots)$, $w$,~$x$,~$y$,~$\dots$ being elective symbols, and if the second member be completely expanded and arranged in a series of terms of the form~$at$, we shall be permitted to equate separately to~$0$ every term in which the modulus~$a$ does not satisfy the condition \[ a^{n} = a, \] and to leave for the value of~$w$ the sum of the remaining terms. As the nature of the demonstration of this Proposition is quite unaffected by the number of the terms in the second member, we will for simplicity confine ourselves to the supposition of there being four, and suppose that the moduli of the two first only, satisfy the index law. We have then \[ w = a_{1}t_{1} + a_{2}t_{2} + a_{3}t_{3} + a_{4}t_{4}, \Tag{(61)} \] with the relations \[ a_{1}^{n} = a_{1},\quad a_{2}^{n} = a_{2}, \] in addition to the two sets of relations connecting $t_{1}$,~$t_{2}$, $t_{3}$,~$t_{4}$, in accordance with \Eqref{(55)}~and~\Eqref{(56)}. Squaring~\Eqref{(61)}, we have \[ w = a_{1}t_{1} + a_{2}t_{2} + a_{3}^{2}t_{3} + a_{4}^{2}t_{4}, \] and subtracting~\Eqref{(61)} from this, \[ (a_{3}^{2} - a_{3})t_{3} + (a_{4}^{2} - a_{4})t_{4} = 0; \] and it being an hypothesis, that the coefficients of these terms do not vanish, we have, by \PropRef{2}, \[ t_{3} = 0,\quad t_{4} = 0, \Tag{(62)} \] whence \Eqref{(61)}~becomes \[ w = a_{1}t_{1} + a_{2}t_{2}. \] The utility of this Proposition will hereafter appear. \PageSep{67} \Prop{4.} The functions $t_{1}t_{2}\dots t_{r}$ being mutually exclusive, we shall always have \[ \psi(a_{1}t_{1} + a_{2}t_{2} \dots + a_{r}t_{r}) = \psi(a_{1})t_{1} + \psi(a_{2})t_{2} \dots + \psi(a_{r})t_{r}, \Tag{(63)} \] whatever may be the values of $a_{1}a_{2}\dots a_{r}$ or the form of~$\psi$. %[** TN: Paragraph not indented in the original] Let the function $a_{1}t_{1} + a_{2}t_{2} \dots + a_{r}t_{r}$ be represented by~$\phi(xy\dots)$, then the moduli $a_{1}a_{2}\dots a_{r}$ will be given by the expressions \[ \phi(11\dots),\quad \phi(10\dots),\quad (\dots)\ \phi(00\dots). \] Also \begin{align*} &\phantom{{}={}}\psi(a_{1}t_{1} + a_{2}t_{2} \dots + a_{r}t_{r}) = \psi\bigl\{\phi(xy\dots)\bigr\} \\ &= \psi\bigl\{\phi(11\dots)\bigr\}xy\dots + \psi\bigl\{\phi(10\dots)\bigr\}x(1 - y)\dots \\ &\qquad+ \psi\bigl\{\phi(00\dots)\bigr\}(1 - x)(1 - y)\dots \\ &= \psi(a_{1})xy\dots + \psi(a_{2})x(1 - y)\dots + \psi(a_{r})(1 - x)(1 - y)\dots \\ &= \psi(a_{1})t_{1} + \psi(a_{2})t_{2}\dots + \psi(a_{r})t_{r}. \Tag{(64)} \end{align*} It would not be difficult to extend the list of interesting properties, of which the above are examples. But those which we have noticed are sufficient for our present requirements. The following Proposition may serve as an illustration of their utility. \Prop{5.} Whatever process of reasoning we apply to a single given Proposition, the result will either be the same Proposition or a limitation of it. Let us represent the equation of the given Proposition under its most general form, \[ a_{1}t_{1} + a_{2}t_{2} \dots + a_{r}t_{r} = 0, \Tag{(65)} \] resolvable into as many equations of the form $t = 0$ as there are moduli which do not vanish. Now the most general transformation of this equation is \[ \psi(a_{1}t_{1} + a_{2}t_{2} \dots + a_{r}t_{r}) = \psi(0), \Tag{(66)} \] provided that we attribute to~$\psi$ a perfectly arbitrary character, allowing it even to involve new elective symbols, having \emph{any proposed relation} to the original ones. \PageSep{68} The development of~\Eqref{(66)} gives, by the last Proposition, \[ \psi(a_{1})t_{1} + \psi(a_{2})t_{2}\dots + \psi(a_{r})t_{r} = \psi(0). \] To reduce this to the general form of reference, it is only necessary to observe that since \[ t_{1} + t_{2} \dots + t_{r} = 1, \] we may write for~$\psi(0)$, \[ \psi(0)(t_{1} + t_{2} \dots + t_{r}), \] whence, on substitution and transposition, \[ \bigl\{\psi(a_{1}) - \psi(0)\bigr\}t_{1} + \bigl\{\psi(a_{2}) - \psi(0)\bigr\}t_{2} \dots + \bigl\{\psi(a_{r}) - \psi(0)\bigr\}t_{r} = 0. \] From which it appears, that if $a$~be any modulus of the original equation, the corresponding modulus of the transformed equation will be \[ \psi(a) - \psi(0). \] If $a = 0$, then $\psi(a) - \psi(0) = \psi(0) - \psi(0) = 0$, whence there are no \emph{new terms} in the transformed equation, and therefore there are no \emph{new Propositions} given by equating its constituent members to~$0$. Again, since $\psi(a) - \psi(0)$ may vanish without $a$~vanishing, terms may be wanting in the transformed equation which existed in the primitive. Thus some of the constituent truths of the original Proposition may entirely disappear from the interpretation of the final result. Lastly, if $\psi(a) - \psi(0)$ do not vanish, it must either be a numerical constant, or it must involve new elective symbols. In the former case, the term in which it is found will give \[ t = 0, \] which is one of the constituents of the original equation: in the latter case we shall have \[ \bigl\{\psi(a\Typo{}{)} - \psi(0)\bigr\}t = 0, \] in which $t$~has a limiting factor. The interpretation of this equation, therefore, is a limitation of the interpretation of~\Eqref{(65)}. \PageSep{69} The purport of the last investigation will be more apparent to the mathematician than to the logician. As from any mathematical equation an infinite number of others may be deduced, it seemed to be necessary to shew that when the original equation expresses a logical Proposition, every member of the derived series, even when obtained by expansion under a functional sign, admits of exact and consistent interpretation. \PageSep{70} \Chapter{Of the Solution of Elective Equations.} \First{In} whatever way an elective symbol, considered as unknown, may be involved in a proposed equation, it is possible to assign its complete value in terms of the remaining elective symbols considered as known. It is to be observed of such equations, that from the very nature of elective symbols, they are necessarily linear, and that their solutions have a very close analogy with those of linear differential equations, arbitrary elective symbols in the one, occupying the place of arbitrary constants in the other. The method of solution we shall in the first place illustrate by particular examples, and, afterwards, apply to the investigation of general theorems. Given $(1 - x)y = 0$, (All~$Y$s are~$X$s), to determine~$y$ in terms of~$x$. As $y$~is a function of~$x$, we may assume $y = vx + v'(1 - x)$, (such being the expression of an arbitrary function of~$x$), the moduli $v$~and~$v'$ remaining to be determined. We have then \[ (1 - x)\bigl\{vx + v'(1 - x)\bigr\} = 0, \] or, on actual multiplication, \[ v'(1 - x) = 0\Typo{:}{;} \] that this may be generally true, without imposing any restriction upon~$x$, we must assume $v' = 0$, and there being no condition to limit~$v$, we have \[ y = vx. \Tag{(67)} \] This is the complete solution of the equation. The condition that $y$~is an elective symbol requires that $v$~should be an elective \PageSep{71} symbol also (since it must satisfy the index law), its interpretation in other respects being arbitrary. Similarly the solution of the equation, $xy = 0$, is \[ y = v(1 - x). \Tag{(68)} \] Given $(1 - x)zy = 0$, (All~$Y$s which are~$Z$s are~$X$s), to determine~$y$. As $y$~is a function of $x$~and~$z$, we may assume \[ y = v(1 - x) (1 - z) + v'(1 - x)z + v''x(1 - z) + v'''zx. \] And substituting, we get \[ v'(1 - x)z = 0, \] whence $v' = 0$. The complete solution is therefore \[ y = v(1 - x)(1 - z) + v''x(1 - z) + v'''xz, \Tag{(69)} \] $v'$,~$v''$,~$v'''$, being arbitrary elective symbols, and the rigorous interpretation of this result is, that Every~$Y$ is \emph{either} a not-$X$ and not-$Z$, or an~$X$ and not-$Z$, or an~$X$ and~$Z$. It is deserving of note that the above equation may, in consequence of its linear form, be solved by adding the two particular solutions with reference to $x$~and~$z$; and replacing the arbitrary constants which each involves by an arbitrary function of the other symbol, the result is \[ y = x\phi(z) + (1 - z)\psi(x). \Tag{(70)} \] To shew that this solution is equivalent to the other, it is only necessary to substitute for the arbitrary functions $\phi(z)$, $\psi(x)$, their equivalents \[ wz + w'(1 - z)\quad\text{and}\quad w''x + w'''(1 - x), \] we get \[ y = wxz + (w + w'')x(1 - z) + w'''(1 - x)(1 - z). \] In consequence of the perfectly arbitrary character of $w'$~and~$w''$, we may replace their sum by a single symbol~$w$, whence \[ y = wxz + w'x(1 - z) + w'''(1 - x)(1 - z), \] which agrees with~\Eqref{(69)}. \PageSep{72} The solution of the equation $wx(1 - y)z = 0$, expressed by arbitrary functions, is \[ z = (1 - w) \phi(xy) + (1 - x)\psi(wy) + y\chi(wx). \Tag{(71)} \] These instances may serve to shew the analogy which exists between the solutions of elective equations and those of the corresponding order of linear differential equations. Thus the expression of the integral of a partial differential equation, either by arbitrary functions or by a series with arbitrary coefficients, is in strict analogy with the case presented in the two last examples. To pursue this comparison further would minister to curiosity rather than to utility. We shall prefer to contemplate the problem of the solution of elective equations under its most general aspect, which is the object of the succeeding investigations. To solve the general equation $\phi(xy) = 0$, with reference to~$y$. If we expand the given equation with reference to $x$~and~$y$, we have \[ %[** TN: Equation broken across two lines in the original \phi(00)(1 - x)(1 - y) + \phi(01)(1 - x)y + \phi(10)x(1 - y) + \phi(11)xy = 0, \Tag{(72)} \] the coefficients $\phi(00)$~\etc.\ being numerical constants. Now the general expression of~$y$, as a function of~$x$, is \[ y = vx + v'(1 - x), \] $v$~and~$v'$ being unknown symbols to be determined. Substituting this value in~\Eqref{(72)}, we obtain a result which may be written in the following form, \[ %[** TN: Equation broken across two lines in the original \bigl[\phi(10) + \bigl\{\phi(11) - \phi(10)\bigr\}v\bigr]x + \bigl[\phi(00) + \bigl\{\phi(00) - \phi(00)\bigr\} v'\bigr](1 - x) = 0; \] and in order that this equation may be satisfied without any way restricting the generality of~$x$, we must have \begin{alignat*}{2} \phi(10) &+ \bigl\{\phi(11) - \phi(10)\bigr\}v &&= 0, \\ \phi(00) &+ \bigl\{\phi(01) - \phi(00)\bigr\}v' &&= 0, \end{alignat*} \PageSep{73} from which we deduce \[ v = \frac{\phi(10)}{\phi(10) - \phi(11)}\;,\qquad v' = \frac{\phi(00)}{\phi(01) - \phi(00)}\;, \] wherefore \[ y = \frac{\phi(10)}{\phi(10) - \phi(11)}\, x + \frac{\phi(00)}{\phi(00) - \phi(01)}\, (1 - x). \Tag{(73)} \] Had we expanded the original equation with respect to $y$~only, we should have had \[ \phi(x0) + \bigl\{\phi(x1) - \phi(x0)\bigr\}y = 0; \] but it might have startled those who are unaccustomed to the processes of Symbolical Algebra, had we from this equation deduced \[ y = \frac{\phi(x0)}{\phi(x0) - \phi(x1)}\;, \] because of the apparently meaningless character of the second member. Such a result would however have been perfectly lawful, and the expansion of the second member would have given us the solution above obtained. I shall in the following example employ this method, and shall only remark that those to whom it may appear doubtful, may verify its conclusions by the previous method. To solve the general equation $\phi(xyz) = 0$, or in other words to determine the value of~$z$ as a function of $x$~and~$y$. Expanding the given equation with reference to~$z$, we have \begin{gather*} \phi(xy0) + \bigl\{\phi(xy1) - \phi(xy0)\bigr\}\Chg{·}{}z = 0; \\ \therefore z = \frac{\phi(xy0)}{\phi(xy0) - \phi(xy1)}\;, \Tag{(74)} \end{gather*} and expanding the second member as a function of $x$~and~$y$ by aid of the general theorem, we have \begin{multline*} z = \frac{\phi(110)}{\phi(110) - \phi(111)}\, xy + \frac{\phi(100)}{\phi(100) - \phi(101)}\, x(1 - y) \\ + \frac{\phi(010)}{\phi(010) - \phi(011)}\, (1 - x)y + \frac{\phi(000)}{\phi(000) - \phi(001)}\, (1 - x)(1 - y), \Tag{(75)} \end{multline*} \PageSep{74} and this is the complete solution required. By the same method we may resolve an equation involving any proposed number of elective symbols. In the interpretation of any general solution of this nature, the following cases may present themselves. The values of the moduli $\phi(00)$, $\phi(01)$,~\etc.\ being constant, one or more of the coefficients of the solution may assume the form $\frac{0}{0}$~or~$\frac{1}{0}$. In the former case, the indefinite symbol~$\frac{0}{0}$ must be replaced by an arbitrary elective symbol~$v$. In the latter case, the term, which is multiplied by a factor~$\frac{1}{0}$ (or by any numerical constant except~$1$), must be separately equated to~$0$, and will indicate the existence of a subsidiary Proposition. This is evident from~\Eqref{(62)}. Ex. Given $x(1 - y) = 0$, All~$X$s are~$Y$s, to determine~$y$ as a function of~$x$. Let $\phi(xy) = x(1 - y)$, then $\phi(10) = 1$, $\phi(11) = 0$, $\phi(01) = 0$, $\phi(00) = 0$; whence, by~\Eqref{(73)}, \begin{align*} y &= \frac{1}{1 - 0}\, x + \frac{0}{0 - 0}\, (1 - x) \\ &= x + \tfrac{0}{0}(1 - x) \\ &= x + v(1 - x), \Tag{(76)} \end{align*} $v$~being an arbitrary elective symbol. The interpretation of this result is that the class~$Y$ consists of the entire class~$X$ with an indefinite remainder of not-$X$s. This remainder is indefinite in the highest sense, \ie~it may vary from~$0$ up to the entire class of not-$X$s. Ex. Given $x(1 - z) + z = y$, (the class~$Y$ consists of the entire class~$Z$, with such not-$Z$s as are~$X$s), to find~$Z$. Here $\phi(xyz) = x(1 - z) - y + z$, whence we have the following set of values for the moduli, \begin{alignat*}{4} \phi(110) &= 0,\quad& \phi(111) &= 0,\quad& \phi(100) &= 1,\quad& \phi(101) &= 1, \\ \phi(010) &=-1,\quad& \phi(011) &= 0,\quad& \phi(000) &= 0,\quad& \phi(001) &= 1, \end{alignat*} and substituting these in the general formula~\Eqref{(75)}, we have \[ z = \tfrac{0}{0}xy + \tfrac{1}{0}x(1 - y) + (1 - x)y, \Tag{(77)} \] \PageSep{75} the infinite coefficient of the second term indicates the equation \[ x(1 - y) = 0,\quad\text{All~$X$s are~$Y$s;} \] and the indeterminate coefficient of the first term being replaced by~$v$, an arbitrary elective symbol, we have \[ z = (1 - x)y + vxy, \] the interpretation of which is, that the class~$Z$ consists of all the~$Y$s which are not~$X$s, and an \emph{indefinite} remainder of~$Y$s which are~$X$s. Of course this indefinite remainder may vanish. The two results we have obtained are logical inferences (not very obvious ones) from the original Propositions, and they give us all the information which it contains respecting the class~$Z$, and its constituent elements. Ex. Given $x = y(1 - z) + z(1 - y)$. The class~$X$ consists of all~$Y$s which are not-$Z$s, and all~$Z$s which are not-$Y$s: required the class~$Z$. We have \begin{alignat*}{4} \phi(xyz) &= \rlap{$x - y(1 - z) - z(1 - y)$,} \\ \phi(110) &= 0,\quad& \phi(111) &= 1,\quad& \phi(100) &= 1,\quad& \phi(101) &= 0, \\ % \phi(010) &= -1,\quad& \phi(011) &= 0, & \phi(000) &= 0, & \phi(001) &= -1; \end{alignat*} whence, by substituting in~\Eqref{(75)}, \[ z = x(1 - y) + y(1 - x), \Tag{(78)} \] the interpretation of which is, the class~$Z$ consists of all~$X$s which are not~$Y$s, and of all~$Y$s which are not~$X$s; an inference strictly logical. Ex. Given $y\bigl\{1 - z(1 - x)\bigr\} = 0$, All~$Y$s are~$Z$s and not-$X$s. Proceeding as before to form the moduli, we have, on substitution in the general formulæ, \[ z = \tfrac{1}{0}xy + \tfrac{0}{0}x(1 - y) + y(1 - x) + \tfrac{0}{0}(1 - x)(1 - y), \] or \begin{align*} %[** TN: Unaligned in the original] z &= y(1 - x) + vx(1 - y) + v'(1 - x)(1 - y) \\ &= y(1 - x) + (1 - y)\phi(x), \Tag{(79)} \end{align*} with the relation \[ xy = 0\Typo{:}{;} \] from these it appears that No~$Y$s are~$X$s, and that the class~$Z$ \PageSep{76} consists of all~$Y$s which are not~$X$s, and of an indefinite remainder of not-$Y$s. This method, in combination with Lagrange's method of indeterminate multipliers, may be very elegantly applied to the treatment of simultaneous equations. Our limits only permit us to offer a single example, but the subject is well deserving of further investigation. Given the equations $x(1 - z) = 0$, $z(1 - y) = 0$, All~$X$s are~$Z$s, All~$Z$s are~$Y$s, to determine the complete value of~$z$ with any subsidiary relations connecting $x$~and~$y$. Adding the second equation multiplied by an indeterminate constant~$\lambda$, to the first, we have \[ x(1 - z) + \lambda z(1 - y) = 0, \] whence determining the moduli, and substituting in~\Eqref{(75)}, \[ z = xy + \frac{1}{1 - \lambda}\, x(1 - y) + \tfrac{0}{0}(1 - x)y, \Tag{(80)} \] from which we derive \[ z = xy + v(1 - x)y, \] with the subsidiary relation \[ x(1 - y) = 0\Typo{:}{;} \] the former of these expresses that the class~$Z$ consists of all~$X$s that are~$Y$s, with an indefinite remainder of not-$X$s that are~$Y$s; the latter, that All~$X$s are~$Y$s, being in fact the conclusion of the syllogism of which the two given Propositions are the premises. By assigning an appropriate meaning to our symbols, all the equations we have discussed would admit of interpretation in hypothetical, but it may suffice to have considered them as examples of categoricals. That peculiarity of elective symbols, in virtue of which every elective equation is reducible to a system of equations $t_{1} = 0$, $t_{2} = 0$,~\etc., so constituted, that all the binary products $t_{1}t_{2}$, $t_{1}t_{3}$, \etc., vanish, represents a general doctrine in Logic with reference to the ultimate analysis of Propositions, of which it may be desirable to offer some illustration. \PageSep{77} Any of these constituents $t_{1}$,~$t_{2}$,~\etc.\ consists only of factors of the forms $x$,~$y$,~$\dots$ $1 - w$,~$1 - z$,~\etc. In categoricals it therefore represents a compound class, \ie~a class defined by the presence of certain qualities, and by the absence of certain other qualities. Each constituent equation $t_{1} = 0$,~\etc.\ expresses a denial of the existence of some class so defined, and the different classes are mutually exclusive. \begin{Rule}[] Thus all categorical Propositions are resolvable into a denial of the existence of certain compound classes, no member of one such class being a member of another. \end{Rule} The Proposition, All~$X$s are~$Y$s, expressed by the equation $x(1 - y) = 0$, is resolved into a denial of the existence of a class whose members are~$X$s and not-$Y$s. The Proposition Some~$X$s are~$Y$s, expressed by $v = xy$, is resolvable as follows. On expansion, \begin{gather*} v - xy = vx(1 - y) + vy(1 - x) + v(1 - x)(1 - y) - xy(1 - v); \\ \therefore vx(1 - y) = 0,\quad vy(1 - x) = 0,\quad v(1 - x)(1 - y) = 0,\quad (1 - v)xy = 0. \end{gather*} The three first imply that there is no class whose members belong to a certain unknown Some, and are~1st, $X$s~and not~$Y$s; 2nd, $Y$s~and not~$X$s; 3rd, not-$X$s and not-$Y$s. The fourth implies that there is no class whose members are $X$s~and~$Y$s without belonging to this unknown Some. From the same analysis it appears that \begin{Rule}[]all hypothetical Propositions may be resolved into denials of the coexistence of the truth or falsity of certain assertions. \end{Rule} Thus the Proposition, If $X$~is true, $Y$~is true, is resolvable by its equation $x(1 - y) = 0$, into a denial that the truth of~$X$ and the falsity of~$Y$ coexist. And the Proposition Either $X$~is true, or $Y$~is true, members exclusive, is resolvable into a denial, first, that $X$~and~$Y$ are both true; secondly, that $X$~and~$Y$ are both false. But it may be asked, is not something more than a system of negations necessary to the constitution of an affirmative Proposition? is not a positive element required? Undoubtedly \PageSep{78} there is need of one; and this positive element is supplied in categoricals by the assumption (which may be regarded as a prerequisite of reasoning in such cases) that there \emph{is} a Universe of conceptions, and that each individual it contains either belongs to a proposed class or does not belong to it; in hypotheticals, by the assumption (equally prerequisite) that there is a Universe of conceivable cases, and that any given Proposition is either true or false. Indeed the question of the existence of conceptions (\textgreek{e>i >'esti}) is preliminary to any statement %[** TN: Should be \textgreek{t'i >esti}? Not sufficiently certain to change.] of their qualities or relations (\textgreek{t'i >'esti}).---\textit{Aristotle, Anal.\ Post.}\ lib.~\textsc{ii}.\ cap.~2. It would appear from the above, that Propositions may be regarded as resting at once upon a positive and upon a negative foundation. Nor is such a view either foreign to the spirit of Deductive Reasoning or inappropriate to its Method; the latter ever proceeding by limitations, while the former contemplates the particular as derived from the general. %[** TN: Equation numbering restarts] \Section{Demonstration of the Method of Indeterminate Multipliers, as applied to Simultaneous Elective Equations.} To avoid needless complexity, it will be sufficient to consider the case of three equations involving three elective symbols, those equations being the most general of the kind. It will be seen that the case is marked by every feature affecting the character of the demonstration, which would present itself in the discussion of the more general problem in which the number of equations and the number of variables are both unlimited. Let the given equations be \[ \phi(xyz) = 0,\quad \psi(xyz) = 0,\quad \chi(xyz) = 0. \Tag[app]{(1)} \] Multiplying the second and third of these by the arbitrary constants $h$~and~$k$, and adding to the first, we have \[ \phi(xyz) + h\psi(xyz) + k\chi(xyz) = 0; \Tag[app]{(2)} \] \PageSep{79} and we are to shew, that in solving this equation with reference to any variable~$z$ by the general theorem~\Eqref{(75)}, we shall obtain not only the general value of~$z$ independent of $h$~and~$k$, but also any subsidiary relations which may exist between $x$~and~$y$ independently of~$z$. %[xref] If we represent the general equation~\Eqref[app]{(2)} under the form $F(xyz) = 0$, its solution may by~\Eqref{(75)} be written in the form \[ z = \frac{xy}{1 - \dfrac{F(111)}{F(110)}} + \frac{x(1 - y)}{1 - \dfrac{F(101)}{F(100)}} + \frac{y(1 - x)}{1 - \dfrac{F(011)}{F(010)}} + \frac{(1 - x)(1 - y)}{1 - \dfrac{F(001)}{F(000)}}; \] and we have seen, that any one of these four terms is to be equated to~$0$, whose modulus, which we may represent by~$M$, does not satisfy the condition $M^{n} = M$, or, which is here the same thing, whose modulus has any other value than $0$~or~$1$. Consider the modulus (suppose~$M_{1}$) of the first term, viz. $\dfrac{1}{1 - \dfrac{F(111)}{F(110)}}$, and giving to the symbol~$F$ its full meaning, we have \[ M_{1} = \frac{1}{1 - \dfrac{\phi(111) + h\psi(111) + k\chi(111)} {\phi(110) + h\psi(110) + k\chi(110)}}. \] It is evident that the condition $M_{1}^{n} = M_{1}$ cannot be satisfied unless the right-hand member be independent of $h$~and~$k$; and in order that this may be the case, we must have the function $\dfrac{\phi(111) + h\psi(111) + k\chi(111)} {\phi(110) + h\psi(110) + k\chi(110)}$ independent of $h$~and~$k$. Assume then \[ \frac{\phi(111) + h\psi(111) + k\chi(111)} {\phi(110) + h\psi(110) + k\chi(110)} = c, \] $c$~being independent of $h$~and~$k$; we have, on clearing of fractions and equating coefficients, \[ \phi(111) = c\phi(110),\quad \psi(111) = c\psi(110),\quad \chi(111) = c\chi(110); \] whence, eliminating~$c$, \[ \frac{\phi(111)}{\phi(110)} = \frac{\psi(111)}{\psi(110)} = \frac{\chi(111)}{\chi(110)}, \] \PageSep{80} being equivalent to the triple system \[ \left.\begin{alignedat}{3} &\phi(111)\psi(110) &&- \phi(110)\psi(111) &&= 0\Add{,} \\ &\psi(111)\chi(110) &&- \psi(110)\chi(111) &&= 0\Add{,} \\ &\chi(111)\phi(110) &&- \chi(110)\Typo{\psi}{\phi}(111) &&= 0\Add{;} \end{alignedat} \right\} \Tag[app]{(3)} \] and it appears that if any one of these equations is not satisfied, the modulus~$M_{1}$ will not satisfy the condition $M_{1}^{n} = M_{1}$, whence the first term of the value of~$z$ must be equated to~$0$, and we shall have \[ xy = 0, \] a relation between $x$~and~$y$ independent of~$z$. Now if we expand in terms of~$z$ each pair of the primitive equations~\Eqref[app]{(1)}, we shall have \begin{alignat*}{3} &\phi(xy0) &&+ \bigl\{\phi(xy1) - \phi(xy0)\bigr\}z &&= 0, \\ &\psi(xy0) &&+ \bigl\{\psi(xy1) - \psi(xy0)\bigr\}z &&= 0, \\ &\chi(xy0) &&+ \bigl\{\chi(xy1) - \chi(xy0)\bigr\}z &&= 0, \end{alignat*} and successively eliminating~$z$ between each pair of these equations, we have \begin{alignat*}{3} &\phi(xy1)\psi(xy0) &&- \phi(xy0)\psi(xy1) &&= 0, \\ &\psi(xy1)\chi(xy0) &&- \psi(xy0)\chi(xy1) &&= 0, \\ &\chi(xy1)\phi(xy0) &&- \chi(xy0)\phi(xy1) &&= 0, \end{alignat*} which express all the relations between $x$~and~$y$ that are formed by the elimination of~$z$. Expanding these, and writing in full the first term, we have \begin{alignat*}{3} &\bigl\{\phi(111)\psi(110) &&- \phi(110)\psi(111)\bigr\}xy &&+ \etc. = 0, \\ &\bigl\{\psi(111)\chi(110) &&- \psi(110)\chi(111)\bigr\}xy &&+ \etc. = 0, \\ &\bigl\{\chi(111)\phi(110) &&- \chi(110)\phi(111)\bigr\}xy &&+ \etc. = 0\Typo{:}{;} \end{alignat*} and it appears from \PropRef{2}.\ that if the coefficient of~$xy$ in any of these equations does not vanish, we shall have the equation \[ xy = 0; \] but the coefficients in question are the same as the first members of the system~\Eqref[app]{(3)}, and the two sets of conditions exactly agree. Thus, as respects the first term of the expansion, the method of indeterminate coefficients leads to the same result as ordinary elimination; and it is obvious that from their similarity of form, the same reasoning will apply to all the other terms. \PageSep{81} Suppose, in the second place, that the conditions~\Eqref[app]{(3)} are satisfied so that $M_{1}$~is independent of $h$~and~$k$. It will then indifferently assume the equivalent forms \[ M_{1} = \frac{1}{1 - \dfrac{\phi(111)}{\phi(110)}} = \frac{1}{1 - \dfrac{\psi(111)}{\psi(110)}} = \frac{1}{1 - \dfrac{\chi(111)}{\chi(110)}}\Add{.} \] These are the exact forms of the first modulus in the expanded values of~$z$, deduced from the solution of the three primitive equations singly. If this common value of~$M_{1}$ is $1$ or $\frac{0}{0} = v$, the term will be retained in~$z$; if any other constant value (except~$0$), we have a relation $xy = 0$, not given by elimination, but deducible from the primitive equations singly, and similarly for all the other terms. Thus in every case the expression of the subsidiary relations is a necessary accompaniment of the process of solution. It is evident, upon consideration, that a similar proof will apply to the discussion of a system indefinite as to the number both of its symbols and of its equations. %[** TN: No page break in the original] \Chapter{Postscript.} \First{Some} additional explanations and references which have occurred to me during the printing of this work are subjoined. The remarks on the connexion between Logic and Language, \Pageref{5}, are scarcely sufficiently explicit. Both the one and the other I hold to depend very materially upon our ability to form general notions by the faculty of abstraction. Language is an instrument of Logic, but not an indispensable instrument. To the remarks on Cause, \Pageref{12}, I desire to add the following: Considering Cause as an invariable antecedent in Nature, (which is Brown's view), whether associated or not with the idea of Power, as suggested by Sir~John Herschel, the knowledge of its existence is a knowledge which is properly expressed by the word \emph{that} (\textgreek{t`o Babel and hyphenation patterns for english, usenglishmax, dumylang, noh yphenation, arabic, farsi, croatian, ukrainian, russian, bulgarian, czech, slov ak, danish, dutch, finnish, basque, french, german, ngerman, ibycus, greek, mon ogreek, ancientgreek, hungarian, italian, latin, mongolian, norsk, icelandic, i nterlingua, turkish, coptic, romanian, welsh, serbian, slovenian, estonian, esp eranto, uppersorbian, indonesian, polish, portuguese, spanish, catalan, galicia n, swedish, ukenglish, pinyin, loaded. (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/base/book.cls Document Class: book 2005/09/16 v1.4f Standard LaTeX document class (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/base/bk12.clo File: bk12.clo 2005/09/16 v1.4f Standard LaTeX file (size option) ) \c@part=\count79 \c@chapter=\count80 \c@section=\count81 \c@subsection=\count82 \c@subsubsection=\count83 \c@paragraph=\count84 \c@subparagraph=\count85 \c@figure=\count86 \c@table=\count87 \abovecaptionskip=\skip41 \belowcaptionskip=\skip42 \bibindent=\dimen102 ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/base/inputenc.sty Package: inputenc 2006/05/05 v1.1b Input encoding file \inpenc@prehook=\toks14 \inpenc@posthook=\toks15 (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/base/latin1.def File: latin1.def 2006/05/05 v1.1b Input encoding file )) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/generic/babel/babel.sty Package: babel 2005/11/23 v3.8h The Babel package (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/generic/babel/greek.ldf Language: greek 2005/03/30 v1.3l Greek support from the babel system (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/generic/babel/babel.def File: babel.def 2005/11/23 v3.8h Babel common definitions \babel@savecnt=\count88 \U@D=\dimen103 ) Loading the definitions for the Greek font encoding (/usr/share/texmf-texlive /tex/generic/babel/lgrenc.def File: lgrenc.def 2001/01/30 v2.2e Greek Encoding )) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/generic/babel/english.ldf Language: english 2005/03/30 v3.3o English support from the babel system \l@british = a dialect from \language\l@english \l@UKenglish = a dialect from \language\l@english \l@canadian = a dialect from \language\l@american \l@australian = a dialect from \language\l@british \l@newzealand = a dialect from \language\l@british )) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/base/ifthen.sty Package: ifthen 2001/05/26 v1.1c Standard LaTeX ifthen package (DPC) ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/amsmath/amsmath.sty Package: amsmath 2000/07/18 v2.13 AMS math features \@mathmargin=\skip43 For additional information on amsmath, use the `?' option. (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/amsmath/amstext.sty Package: amstext 2000/06/29 v2.01 (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/amsmath/amsgen.sty File: amsgen.sty 1999/11/30 v2.0 \@emptytoks=\toks16 \ex@=\dimen104 )) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/amsmath/amsbsy.sty Package: amsbsy 1999/11/29 v1.2d \pmbraise@=\dimen105 ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/amsmath/amsopn.sty Package: amsopn 1999/12/14 v2.01 operator names ) \inf@bad=\count89 LaTeX Info: Redefining \frac on input line 211. \uproot@=\count90 \leftroot@=\count91 LaTeX Info: Redefining \overline on input line 307. \classnum@=\count92 \DOTSCASE@=\count93 LaTeX Info: Redefining \ldots on input line 379. LaTeX Info: Redefining \dots on input line 382. LaTeX Info: Redefining \cdots on input line 467. \Mathstrutbox@=\box26 \strutbox@=\box27 \big@size=\dimen106 LaTeX Font Info: Redeclaring font encoding OML on input line 567. LaTeX Font Info: Redeclaring font encoding OMS on input line 568. \macc@depth=\count94 \c@MaxMatrixCols=\count95 \dotsspace@=\muskip10 \c@parentequation=\count96 \dspbrk@lvl=\count97 \tag@help=\toks17 \row@=\count98 \column@=\count99 \maxfields@=\count100 \andhelp@=\toks18 \eqnshift@=\dimen107 \alignsep@=\dimen108 \tagshift@=\dimen109 \tagwidth@=\dimen110 \totwidth@=\dimen111 \lineht@=\dimen112 \@envbody=\toks19 \multlinegap=\skip44 \multlinetaggap=\skip45 \mathdisplay@stack=\toks20 LaTeX Info: Redefining \[ on input line 2666. LaTeX Info: Redefining \] on input line 2667. ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/amsfonts/amssymb.sty Package: amssymb 2002/01/22 v2.2d (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/amsfonts/amsfonts.sty Package: amsfonts 2001/10/25 v2.2f \symAMSa=\mathgroup4 \symAMSb=\mathgroup5 LaTeX Font Info: Overwriting math alphabet `\mathfrak' in version `bold' (Font) U/euf/m/n --> U/euf/b/n on input line 132. )) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/base/alltt.sty Package: alltt 1997/06/16 v2.0g defines alltt environment ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/tools/array.sty Package: array 2005/08/23 v2.4b Tabular extension package (FMi) \col@sep=\dimen113 \extrarowheight=\dimen114 \NC@list=\toks21 \extratabsurround=\skip46 \backup@length=\skip47 ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/tools/indentfirst.sty Package: indentfirst 1995/11/23 v1.03 Indent first paragraph (DPC) ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/footmisc/footmisc.sty Package: footmisc 2005/03/17 v5.3d a miscellany of footnote facilities \FN@temptoken=\toks22 \footnotemargin=\dimen115 \c@pp@next@reset=\count101 \c@@fnserial=\count102 Package footmisc Info: Declaring symbol style bringhurst on input line 817. Package footmisc Info: Declaring symbol style chicago on input line 818. Package footmisc Info: Declaring symbol style wiley on input line 819. Package footmisc Info: Declaring symbol style lamport-robust on input line 823. Package footmisc Info: Declaring symbol style lamport* on input line 831. Package footmisc Info: Declaring symbol style lamport*-robust on input line 840 . ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/caption/caption.sty Package: caption 2007/01/07 v3.0k Customising captions (AR) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/caption/caption3.sty Package: caption3 2007/01/07 v3.0k caption3 kernel (AR) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/graphics/keyval.sty Package: keyval 1999/03/16 v1.13 key=value parser (DPC) \KV@toks@=\toks23 ) \captionmargin=\dimen116 \captionmarginx=\dimen117 \captionwidth=\dimen118 \captionindent=\dimen119 \captionparindent=\dimen120 \captionhangindent=\dimen121 )) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/tools/calc.sty Package: calc 2005/08/06 v4.2 Infix arithmetic (KKT,FJ) \calc@Acount=\count103 \calc@Bcount=\count104 \calc@Adimen=\dimen122 \calc@Bdimen=\dimen123 \calc@Askip=\skip48 \calc@Bskip=\skip49 LaTeX Info: Redefining \setlength on input line 75. LaTeX Info: Redefining \addtolength on input line 76. \calc@Ccount=\count105 \calc@Cskip=\skip50 ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/fancyhdr/fancyhdr.sty \fancy@headwidth=\skip51 \f@ncyO@elh=\skip52 \f@ncyO@erh=\skip53 \f@ncyO@olh=\skip54 \f@ncyO@orh=\skip55 \f@ncyO@elf=\skip56 \f@ncyO@erf=\skip57 \f@ncyO@olf=\skip58 \f@ncyO@orf=\skip59 ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/geometry/geometry.sty Package: geometry 2002/07/08 v3.2 Page Geometry \Gm@cnth=\count106 \Gm@cntv=\count107 \c@Gm@tempcnt=\count108 \Gm@bindingoffset=\dimen124 \Gm@wd@mp=\dimen125 \Gm@odd@mp=\dimen126 \Gm@even@mp=\dimen127 \Gm@dimlist=\toks24 (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/xelatex/xetexconfig/geometry.cfg)) (/usr/share/te xmf-texlive/tex/latex/hyperref/hyperref.sty Package: hyperref 2007/02/07 v6.75r Hypertext links for LaTeX \@linkdim=\dimen128 \Hy@linkcounter=\count109 \Hy@pagecounter=\count110 (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/hyperref/pd1enc.def File: pd1enc.def 2007/02/07 v6.75r Hyperref: PDFDocEncoding definition (HO) ) (/etc/texmf/tex/latex/config/hyperref.cfg File: hyperref.cfg 2002/06/06 v1.2 hyperref configuration of TeXLive ) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/oberdiek/kvoptions.sty Package: kvoptions 2006/08/22 v2.4 Connects package keyval with LaTeX options ( HO) ) Package hyperref Info: Option `hyperfootnotes' set `false' on input line 2238. Package hyperref Info: Option `bookmarks' set `true' on input line 2238. Package hyperref Info: Option `linktocpage' set `false' on input line 2238. Package hyperref Info: Option `pdfdisplaydoctitle' set `true' on input line 223 8. Package hyperref Info: Option `pdfpagelabels' set `true' on input line 2238. Package hyperref Info: Option `bookmarksopen' set `true' on input line 2238. Package hyperref Info: Option `colorlinks' set `true' on input line 2238. Package hyperref Info: Hyper figures OFF on input line 2288. Package hyperref Info: Link nesting OFF on input line 2293. Package hyperref Info: Hyper index ON on input line 2296. Package hyperref Info: Plain pages OFF on input line 2303. Package hyperref Info: Backreferencing OFF on input line 2308. Implicit mode ON; LaTeX internals redefined Package hyperref Info: Bookmarks ON on input line 2444. (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/ltxmisc/url.sty \Urlmuskip=\muskip11 Package: url 2005/06/27 ver 3.2 Verb mode for urls, etc. ) LaTeX Info: Redefining \url on input line 2599. \Fld@menulength=\count111 \Field@Width=\dimen129 \Fld@charsize=\dimen130 \Choice@toks=\toks25 \Field@toks=\toks26 Package hyperref Info: Hyper figures OFF on input line 3102. Package hyperref Info: Link nesting OFF on input line 3107. Package hyperref Info: Hyper index ON on input line 3110. Package hyperref Info: backreferencing OFF on input line 3117. Package hyperref Info: Link coloring ON on input line 3120. \Hy@abspage=\count112 \c@Item=\count113 ) *hyperref using driver hpdftex* (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/hyperref/hpdftex.def File: hpdftex.def 2007/02/07 v6.75r Hyperref driver for pdfTeX \Fld@listcount=\count114 ) \TmpLen=\skip60 \c@ChapNo=\count115 (./36884-t.aux LaTeX Font Info: Try loading font information for LGR+cmr on input line 22. (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/generic/babel/lgrcmr.fd File: lgrcmr.fd 2001/01/30 v2.2e Greek Computer Modern )) \openout1 = `36884-t.aux'. LaTeX Font Info: Checking defaults for OML/cmm/m/it on input line 457. LaTeX Font Info: ... okay on input line 457. LaTeX Font Info: Checking defaults for T1/cmr/m/n on input line 457. LaTeX Font Info: ... okay on input line 457. LaTeX Font Info: Checking defaults for OT1/cmr/m/n on input line 457. LaTeX Font Info: ... okay on input line 457. LaTeX Font Info: Checking defaults for OMS/cmsy/m/n on input line 457. LaTeX Font Info: ... okay on input line 457. LaTeX Font Info: Checking defaults for OMX/cmex/m/n on input line 457. LaTeX Font Info: ... okay on input line 457. LaTeX Font Info: Checking defaults for U/cmr/m/n on input line 457. LaTeX Font Info: ... okay on input line 457. LaTeX Font Info: Checking defaults for LGR/cmr/m/n on input line 457. LaTeX Font Info: ... okay on input line 457. LaTeX Font Info: Checking defaults for PD1/pdf/m/n on input line 457. LaTeX Font Info: ... okay on input line 457. (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/ragged2e/ragged2e.sty Package: ragged2e 2003/03/25 v2.04 ragged2e Package (MS) (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/everysel/everysel.sty Package: everysel 1999/06/08 v1.03 EverySelectfont Package (MS) LaTeX Info: Redefining \selectfont on input line 125. ) \CenteringLeftskip=\skip61 \RaggedLeftLeftskip=\skip62 \RaggedRightLeftskip=\skip63 \CenteringRightskip=\skip64 \RaggedLeftRightskip=\skip65 \RaggedRightRightskip=\skip66 \CenteringParfillskip=\skip67 \RaggedLeftParfillskip=\skip68 \RaggedRightParfillskip=\skip69 \JustifyingParfillskip=\skip70 \CenteringParindent=\skip71 \RaggedLeftParindent=\skip72 \RaggedRightParindent=\skip73 \JustifyingParindent=\skip74 ) Package caption Info: hyperref package v6.74m (or newer) detected on input line 457. -------------------- Geometry parameters paper: class default landscape: -- twocolumn: -- twoside: true asymmetric: -- h-parts: 9.03374pt, 379.4175pt, 9.03375pt v-parts: 1.26749pt, 538.85623pt, 1.90128pt hmarginratio: 1:1 vmarginratio: 2:3 lines: -- heightrounded: -- bindingoffset: 0.0pt truedimen: -- includehead: true includefoot: true includemp: -- driver: pdftex -------------------- Page layout dimensions and switches \paperwidth 397.48499pt \paperheight 542.025pt \textwidth 379.4175pt \textheight 476.98244pt \oddsidemargin -63.23625pt \evensidemargin -63.23624pt \topmargin -71.0025pt \headheight 12.0pt \headsep 19.8738pt \footskip 30.0pt \marginparwidth 98.0pt \marginparsep 7.0pt \columnsep 10.0pt \skip\footins 10.8pt plus 4.0pt minus 2.0pt \hoffset 0.0pt \voffset 0.0pt \mag 1000 \@twosidetrue \@mparswitchtrue (1in=72.27pt, 1cm=28.45pt) ----------------------- (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/graphics/color.sty Package: color 2005/11/14 v1.0j Standard LaTeX Color (DPC) (/etc/texmf/tex/latex/config/color.cfg File: color.cfg 2007/01/18 v1.5 color configuration of teTeX/TeXLive ) Package color Info: Driver file: pdftex.def on input line 130. (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/pdftex-def/pdftex.def File: pdftex.def 2007/01/08 v0.04d Graphics/color for pdfTeX \Gread@gobject=\count116 (/usr/share/texmf/tex/context/base/supp-pdf.tex [Loading MPS to PDF converter (version 2006.09.02).] \scratchcounter=\count117 \scratchdimen=\dimen131 \scratchbox=\box28 \nofMPsegments=\count118 \nofMParguments=\count119 \everyMPshowfont=\toks27 \MPscratchCnt=\count120 \MPscratchDim=\dimen132 \MPnumerator=\count121 \everyMPtoPDFconversion=\toks28 ))) Package hyperref Info: Link coloring ON on input line 457. (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/hyperref/nameref.sty Package: nameref 2006/12/27 v2.28 Cross-referencing by name of section (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/oberdiek/refcount.sty Package: refcount 2006/02/20 v3.0 Data extraction from references (HO) ) \c@section@level=\count122 ) LaTeX Info: Redefining \ref on input line 457. LaTeX Info: Redefining \pageref on input line 457. (./36884-t.out) (./36884-t.out) \@outlinefile=\write3 \openout3 = `36884-t.out'. Overfull \hbox (40.57884pt too wide) in paragraph at lines 483--483 []\OT1/cmtt/m/n/10 *** START OF THIS PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK THE MATHEMATICAL A NALYSIS OF LOGIC ***[] [] LaTeX Font Info: Try loading font information for U+msa on input line 485. (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/amsfonts/umsa.fd File: umsa.fd 2002/01/19 v2.2g AMS font definitions ) LaTeX Font Info: Try loading font information for U+msb on input line 485. (/usr/share/texmf-texlive/tex/latex/amsfonts/umsb.fd File: umsb.fd 2002/01/19 v2.2g AMS font definitions ) [1 {/var/lib/texmf/fonts/map/pdftex/updmap/pdftex.map}] [2] [1 ] [2] [1 ] [2] [3 ] [4] [5] [6] [7] [8] [9] [10] [11] [12] [13] [14 ] [15] [16] [17] [18] [19 ] [20] [21] [22] [23] [24] [25] [26 ] [27] [28] [29] [30] [31] [32 ] [33] [34] [35] [36] [37] [38] [39] [40] [41] [42] [43] [44] [45] [46] [47] [4 8] [49 ] [50] [51] [52] [53] [54] [55] [56] [57] [58] [59] [60] [61] [62 ] [63] [64] [65] [66] [67] [68] [69] [70] [71] [72] [73 ] [74] [75] [76] [77] [78] [79] [80] [81] [82] [83] [84] [85] [86 ] [87] Overfull \hbox (30.07893pt too wide) in paragraph at lines 4612--4612 []\OT1/cmtt/m/n/10 End of Project Gutenberg's The Mathematical Analysis of Logi c, by George Boole[] [] Overfull \hbox (30.07893pt too wide) in paragraph at lines 4614--4614 []\OT1/cmtt/m/n/10 *** END OF THIS PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK THE MATHEMATICAL ANA LYSIS OF LOGIC ***[] [] [1 ] Overfull \hbox (3.82916pt too wide) in paragraph at lines 4681--4681 []\OT1/cmtt/m/n/10 1.C. The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation ("th e Foundation"[] [] Overfull \hbox (3.82916pt too wide) in paragraph at lines 4686--4686 []\OT1/cmtt/m/n/10 located in the United States, we do not claim a right to pre vent you from[] [] [2] Overfull \hbox (3.82916pt too wide) in paragraph at lines 4691--4691 []\OT1/cmtt/m/n/10 freely sharing Project Gutenberg-tm works in compliance with the terms of[] [] [3] Overfull \hbox (3.82916pt too wide) in paragraph at lines 4754--4754 []\OT1/cmtt/m/n/10 posted on the official Project Gutenberg-tm web site (www.gu tenberg.org),[] [] [4] [5] [6] [7] [8] [9] [10] (./36884-t.aux) *File List* book.cls 2005/09/16 v1.4f Standard LaTeX document class bk12.clo 2005/09/16 v1.4f Standard LaTeX file (size option) inputenc.sty 2006/05/05 v1.1b Input encoding file latin1.def 2006/05/05 v1.1b Input encoding file babel.sty 2005/11/23 v3.8h The Babel package greek.ldf 2005/03/30 v1.3l Greek support from the babel system lgrenc.def 2001/01/30 v2.2e Greek Encoding english.ldf 2005/03/30 v3.3o English support from the babel system ifthen.sty 2001/05/26 v1.1c Standard LaTeX ifthen package (DPC) amsmath.sty 2000/07/18 v2.13 AMS math features amstext.sty 2000/06/29 v2.01 amsgen.sty 1999/11/30 v2.0 amsbsy.sty 1999/11/29 v1.2d amsopn.sty 1999/12/14 v2.01 operator names amssymb.sty 2002/01/22 v2.2d amsfonts.sty 2001/10/25 v2.2f alltt.sty 1997/06/16 v2.0g defines alltt environment array.sty 2005/08/23 v2.4b Tabular extension package (FMi) indentfirst.sty 1995/11/23 v1.03 Indent first paragraph (DPC) footmisc.sty 2005/03/17 v5.3d a miscellany of footnote facilities caption.sty 2007/01/07 v3.0k Customising captions (AR) caption3.sty 2007/01/07 v3.0k caption3 kernel (AR) keyval.sty 1999/03/16 v1.13 key=value parser (DPC) calc.sty 2005/08/06 v4.2 Infix arithmetic (KKT,FJ) fancyhdr.sty geometry.sty 2002/07/08 v3.2 Page Geometry geometry.cfg hyperref.sty 2007/02/07 v6.75r Hypertext links for LaTeX pd1enc.def 2007/02/07 v6.75r Hyperref: PDFDocEncoding definition (HO) hyperref.cfg 2002/06/06 v1.2 hyperref configuration of TeXLive kvoptions.sty 2006/08/22 v2.4 Connects package keyval with LaTeX options (HO ) url.sty 2005/06/27 ver 3.2 Verb mode for urls, etc. hpdftex.def 2007/02/07 v6.75r Hyperref driver for pdfTeX lgrcmr.fd 2001/01/30 v2.2e Greek Computer Modern ragged2e.sty 2003/03/25 v2.04 ragged2e Package (MS) everysel.sty 1999/06/08 v1.03 EverySelectfont Package (MS) color.sty 2005/11/14 v1.0j Standard LaTeX Color (DPC) color.cfg 2007/01/18 v1.5 color configuration of teTeX/TeXLive pdftex.def 2007/01/08 v0.04d Graphics/color for pdfTeX supp-pdf.tex nameref.sty 2006/12/27 v2.28 Cross-referencing by name of section refcount.sty 2006/02/20 v3.0 Data extraction from references (HO) 36884-t.out 36884-t.out umsa.fd 2002/01/19 v2.2g AMS font definitions umsb.fd 2002/01/19 v2.2g AMS font definitions *********** ) Here is how much of TeX's memory you used: 5776 strings out of 94074 77809 string characters out of 1165154 153122 words of memory out of 1500000 8611 multiletter control sequences out of 10000+50000 18517 words of font info for 66 fonts, out of 1200000 for 2000 645 hyphenation exceptions out of 8191 34i,22n,43p,258b,497s stack positions out of 5000i,500n,6000p,200000b,5000s Output written on 36884-t.pdf (101 pages, 429585 bytes). PDF statistics: 1028 PDF objects out of 1200 (max. 8388607) 358 named destinations out of 1000 (max. 131072) 121 words of extra memory for PDF output out of 10000 (max. 10000000)